HoareHoare Logic
(* $Date: 2012-05-12 10:20:28 -0400 (Sat, 12 May 2012) $ *)
Require Export Imp.
In the past couple of chapters, we've begun applying the
mathematical tools developed in the first part of the course to
studying the theory of a small programming language, Imp.
In this chapter, we'll take this last idea further. We'll
develop a reasoning system called Floyd-Hoare Logic — commonly
shortened to just Hoare Logic — in which each of the syntactic
constructs of Imp is equipped with a single, generic "proof rule"
that can be used to reason about programs involving this
construct.
Hoare Logic originates in the 1960s, and it continues to be the
subject of intensive research right up to the present day. It
lies at the core of a huge variety of tools that are now being
used to specify and verify real software systems.
- We defined a type of abstract syntax trees for Imp, together
with an evaluation relation (a partial function on states)
that specifies the operational semantics of programs.
- We proved a number of metatheoretic properties — "meta" in
the sense that they are properties of the language as a whole,
rather than properties of particular programs in the language.
These included:
- determinism of evaluation
- equivalence of some different ways of writing down the
definitions (e.g. functional and relational definitions of
arithmetic expression evaluation)
- guaranteed termination of certain classes of programs
- correctness (in the sense of preserving meaning) of a number
of useful program transformations
- behavioral equivalence of programs (in the optional chapter
Equiv).
- determinism of evaluation
- We saw a couple of examples of program verification — using the precise definition of Imp to prove formally that certain particular programs (e.g., factorial and slow subtraction) satisfied particular specifications of their behavior.
Hoare Logic
Assertions
Definition Assertion := state → Prop.
Exercise: 1 star (assertions)
Paraphrase the following assertions in English.
1) fun st => st X = 3
2) fun st => st X = x
3) fun st => st X <= st Y
4) fun st => st X = 3 ∨ st X <= st Y
5) fun st => st Z * st Z <= x ∧ ~ (((S (st Z)) * (S (st Z))) <= x)
6) fun st => True
7) fun st => False
2) fun st => st X = x
3) fun st => st X <= st Y
4) fun st => st X = 3 ∨ st X <= st Y
5) fun st => st Z * st Z <= x ∧ ~ (((S (st Z)) * (S (st Z))) <= x)
6) fun st => True
7) fun st => False
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
This way of writing assertions is formally correct — it
precisely captures what we mean, and it is exactly what we will
use in Coq proofs. We'll also want a lighter, less formal
notation for discussing examples, since this one is a bit
heavy: (1) every single assertion that we ever write is going to
begin with fun st => ; and (2) this state st is the only one that
we ever use to look up variables (we will never need to talk about
two different memory states at the same time). So, when writing down
assertions informally, we'll make some simplifications:
drop the initial fun st =>, and write just X instead of st X. Informally, instead of writing
fun st => (st Z) * (st Z) <= x ∧ ~ ((S (st Z)) * (S (st Z)) <= x)
we'll write just
Z * Z <= x ∧ ~((S Z) * (S Z) <= x).
Hoare Triples
- "If command c is started in a state satisfying assertion P, and if c eventually terminates, then the final state is guaranteed to satisfy the assertion Q."
Definition hoare_triple (P:Assertion) (c:com) (Q:Assertion) : Prop :=
∀st st',
c / st ⇓ st' →
P st →
Q st'.
Since we'll be working a lot with Hoare triples, it's useful to
have a compact notation:
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
(Traditionally, Hoare triples are written {P} c {Q}, but single
braces are already used for other things in Coq.)
Notation "{{ P }} c {{ Q }}" := (hoare_triple P c Q)
(at level 90, c at next level)
: hoare_spec_scope.
Open Scope hoare_spec_scope.
(The hoare_spec_scope annotation here tells Coq that this
notation is not global but is intended to be used in particular
contexts. The Open Scope tells Coq that this file is one such
context. The first notation — with missing postcondition — will
not actually be used for a while; it's just a placeholder for a
notation that we'll want to define later, when we discuss
decorated programs.)
Exercise: 1 star (triples)
Paraphrase the following Hoare triples in English.
1) {{True}} c {{X = 5}}
2) {{X = x}} c {{X = x + 5)}}
3) {{X <= Y}} c {{Y <= X}}
4) {{True}} c {{False}}
5) {{X = x}}
c
{{Y = real_fact x}}.
6) {{True}}
c
{{(Z * Z) <= x ∧ ~ (((S Z) * (S Z)) <= x)}}
2) {{X = x}} c {{X = x + 5)}}
3) {{X <= Y}} c {{Y <= X}}
4) {{True}} c {{False}}
5) {{X = x}}
c
{{Y = real_fact x}}.
6) {{True}}
c
{{(Z * Z) <= x ∧ ~ (((S Z) * (S Z)) <= x)}}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 1 star (valid_triples)
Which of the following Hoare triples are valid — i.e., the claimed relation between P, c, and Q is true?
1) {{True}} X ::= 5 {{X = 5}}
2) {{X = 2}} X ::= X + 1 {{X = 3}}
3) {{True}} X ::= 5; Y ::= 0 {{X = 5}}
4) {{X = 2 ∧ X = 3}} X ::= 5 {{X = 0}}
5) {{True}} SKIP {{False}}
6) {{False}} SKIP {{True}}
7) {{True}} WHILE True DO SKIP END {{False}}
8) {{X = 0}}
WHILE X == 0 DO X ::= X + 1 END
{{X = 1}}
9) {{X = 1}}
WHILE X <> 0 DO X ::= X + 1 END
{{X = 100}}
2) {{X = 2}} X ::= X + 1 {{X = 3}}
3) {{True}} X ::= 5; Y ::= 0 {{X = 5}}
4) {{X = 2 ∧ X = 3}} X ::= 5 {{X = 0}}
5) {{True}} SKIP {{False}}
6) {{False}} SKIP {{True}}
7) {{True}} WHILE True DO SKIP END {{False}}
8) {{X = 0}}
WHILE X == 0 DO X ::= X + 1 END
{{X = 1}}
9) {{X = 1}}
WHILE X <> 0 DO X ::= X + 1 END
{{X = 100}}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
(Note that we're using informal mathematical notations for
expressions inside of commands, for readability. We'll continue
doing so throughout the chapter.)
To get us warmed up, here are two simple facts about Hoare
triples.
Theorem hoare_post_true : ∀(P Q : Assertion) c,
(∀st, Q st) →
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P Q c H. unfold hoare_triple.
intros st st' Heval HP.
apply H. Qed.
Theorem hoare_pre_false : ∀(P Q : Assertion) c,
(∀st, ~(P st)) →
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P Q c H. unfold hoare_triple.
intros st st' Heval HP.
unfold not in H. apply H in HP.
inversion HP. Qed.
Weakest Preconditions
{{ False }} X ::= Y + 1 {{ X <= 5 }}
is not very interesting: it is perfectly valid, but it tells us
nothing useful. Since the precondition isn't satisfied by any
state, it doesn't describe any situations where we can use the
command X ::= Y + 1 to achieve the postcondition X <= 5.
{{ Y <= 4 ∧ Z = 0 }} X ::= Y + 1 {{ X <= 5 }}
is useful: it tells us that, if we can somehow create a situation
in which we know that Y <= 4 ∧ Z = 0, then running this command
will produce a state satisfying the postcondition. However, this
triple is still not as useful as it could be, because the Z = 0
clause in the precondition actually has nothing to do with the
postcondition X <= 5. The most useful triple (for a given
command and postcondition) is this one:
{{ Y <= 4 }} X ::= Y + 1 {{ X <= 5 }}
In other words, Y <= 4 is the weakest valid precondition of
the command X ::= Y + 1 for the postcondition X <= 5.
- {{P}} c {{Q}}, and
- whenever P' is an assertion such that {{P'}} c {{Q}}, we have P' st implies P st for all states st.
Definition assert_implies (P Q : Assertion) : Prop :=
∀st, P st → Q st.
We will write P ⇝ Q (in ASCII, P ~~> Q) for assert_implies
P Q.
Notation "P ⇝ Q" := (assert_implies P Q) (at level 80).
Notation "P ↭ Q" := (P ⇝ Q ∧ Q ⇝ P) (at level 80).
Exercise: 1 star (wp)
What are the weakest preconditions of the following commands for the following postconditions?
1) {{ ? }} SKIP {{ X = 5 }}
2) {{ ? }} X ::= Y + Z {{ X = 5 }}
3) {{ ? }} X ::= Y {{ X = Y }}
4) {{ ? }}
IFB X == 0 THEN Y ::= Z + 1 ELSE Y ::= W + 2 FI
{{ Y = 5 }}
5) {{ ? }}
X ::= 5
{{ X = 0 }}
6) {{ ? }}
WHILE True DO X ::= 0 END
{{ X = 0 }}
2) {{ ? }} X ::= Y + Z {{ X = 5 }}
3) {{ ? }} X ::= Y {{ X = Y }}
4) {{ ? }}
IFB X == 0 THEN Y ::= Z + 1 ELSE Y ::= W + 2 FI
{{ Y = 5 }}
5) {{ ? }}
X ::= 5
{{ X = 0 }}
6) {{ ? }}
WHILE True DO X ::= 0 END
{{ X = 0 }}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (is_wp_formal)
Weakest preconditions can be defined formally as follows:Definition is_wp P c Q :=
{{P}} c {{Q}} ∧
∀P', {{P'}} c {{Q}} → (∀st, P' st → P st).
Prove formally using the definition of hoare_triple that Y <= 4
is indeed the weakest precondition of X ::= Y + 1 with respect to
postcondition X <= 5.
Theorem is_wp_example :
is_wp (fun st => st Y <= 4)
(X ::= APlus (AId Y) (ANum 1)) (fun st => st X <= 5).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Proof Rules
Assignment
{{ Y = 1 }} X ::= Y {{ X = 1 }}
In English: if we start out in a state where the value of Y
is 1 and we assign Y to X, then we'll finish in a
state where X is 1. That is, the property of being equal
to 1 gets transferred from Y to X.
{{ Y + Z = 1 }} X ::= Y + Z {{ X = 1 }}
the same property (being equal to one) gets transferred to
X from the expression Y + Z on the right-hand side of
the assignment.
{{ a = 1 }} X ::= a {{ X = 1 }}
is a valid Hoare triple.
{{ Q(a) }} X ::= a {{ Q(X) }}
is a valid Hoare triple.
{{ Q where a is substituted for X }} X ::= a {{ Q }}
For example, these are valid applications of the assignment
rule:
{{ (X <= 5) where X + 1 is substituted for X
i.e., X + 1 <= 5 }}
X ::= X + 1
{{ X <= 5 }}
{{ (X = 3) where 3 is substituted for X
i.e., 3 = 3}}
X ::= 3
{{ X = 3 }}
{{ (0 <= X ∧ X <= 5) where 3 is substituted for X
i.e., (0 <= 3 ∧ 3 <= 5)}}
X ::= 3
{{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
i.e., X + 1 <= 5 }}
X ::= X + 1
{{ X <= 5 }}
{{ (X = 3) where 3 is substituted for X
i.e., 3 = 3}}
X ::= 3
{{ X = 3 }}
{{ (0 <= X ∧ X <= 5) where 3 is substituted for X
i.e., (0 <= 3 ∧ 3 <= 5)}}
X ::= 3
{{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
Definition assn_sub X a Q : Assertion :=
fun (st : state) =>
Q (update st X (aeval st a)).
We ask that Q holds for the state obtained by assigning a to
X, i.e. the updated state in which X is bound to the result of
evaluating a. Since we've chosen to represent assertions using
Coq propositions, this is the only way we can "substitute" a
variable inside an assertion.
Now the precise proof rule for assignment:
(hoare_asgn) | |
{{assn_sub X a Q}} X::=a {{Q}} |
Theorem hoare_asgn : ∀Q X a,
{{assn_sub X a Q}} (X ::= a) {{Q}}.
Proof.
unfold hoare_triple.
intros Q X a st st' HE HQ.
inversion HE. subst.
unfold assn_sub in HQ. assumption. Qed.
Here's a first formal proof using this rule.
Example assn_sub_example :
{{assn_sub X (ANum 3) (fun st => st X = 3)}}
(X ::= (ANum 3))
{{fun st => st X = 3}}.
Proof.
apply hoare_asgn. Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_asgn_examples)
Translate these informal Hoare triples...
{{ assn_sub X (X + 1) (X <= 5) }} X ::= X + 1 {{ X <= 5 }}
{{ assn_sub X 3 (0 <= X ∧ X <= 5) }} X ::= 3 {{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
...into formal statements and use hoare_asgn to prove them.
{{ assn_sub X 3 (0 <= X ∧ X <= 5) }} X ::= 3 {{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Give a counterexample showing that this rule is incorrect
(informally). Hint: The rule universally quantifies over the
arithmetic expression a, and your counterexample needs to
exhibit an a for which the rule doesn't work.
Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_asgn_wrong)
The assignment rule looks backward to almost everyone the first time they see it. If it still seems backward to you, it may help to think a little about alternative "forward" rules. Here is a seemingly natural one:(hoare_asgn_wrong) | |
{{ True }} X ::= a {{ X = a }} |
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Note that we use the original value of X to reconstruct the
state st' before the assignment took place. Prove that this rule
is correct (the first hypothesis is the functional extensionality
axiom, which you will need at some point). Also note that this
rule is more complicated than hoare_asgn.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (hoare_asgn_fwd)
However, using an auxiliary variable x to remember the original value of X we can define a Hoare rule for assignment that does, intuitively, "work forwards" rather than backwards.(hoare_asgn_fwd) | |
{{fun st => Q st ∧ st X = x}} | |
X ::= a | |
{{fun st => Q st' ∧ st X = aeval st' a }} | |
(where st' = update st X x) |
Theorem hoare_asgn_fwd :
(∀{X Y: Type} {f g : X → Y}, (∀(x: X), f x = g x) → f = g) →
∀x a Q,
{{fun st => Q st ∧ st X = x}}
X ::= a
{{fun st => Q (update st X x) ∧ st X = aeval (update st X x) a }}.
Proof.
intros functional_extensionality v a Q.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_asgn_weakest)
Show that the precondition in the rule hoare_asgn is in fact the weakest precondition.Theorem hoare_asgn_weakest : ∀P X a Q,
{{P}} (X ::= a) {{Q}} →
P ⇝ assn_sub X a Q.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Consequence
{{assn_sub X 3 (X = 3)}} X ::= 3 {{X = 3}},
follows directly from the assignment rule,
{{True}} X ::= 3 {{X = 3}}.
does not. This triple is also valid, but it is not an instance of
hoare_asgn because True and assn_sub X 3 (X = 3) are not
syntactically equal assertions. However, they are logically
equivalent, so if one triple is valid, then the other must
certainly be as well. We could capture this observation with the
following rule:
{{P'}} c {{Q}} | |
P ↭ P' | (hoare_consequence_pre_equiv) |
{{P}} c {{Q}} |
{{P'}} c {{Q}} | |
P ⇝ P' | (hoare_consequence_pre) |
{{P}} c {{Q}} |
{{P}} c {{Q'}} | |
Q' ⇝ Q | (hoare_consequence_post) |
{{P}} c {{Q}} |
Theorem hoare_consequence_pre : ∀(P P' Q : Assertion) c,
{{P'}} c {{Q}} →
P ⇝ P' →
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P P' Q c Hhoare Himp.
intros st st' Hc HP. apply (Hhoare st st').
assumption. apply Himp. assumption. Qed.
Theorem hoare_consequence_post : ∀(P Q Q' : Assertion) c,
{{P}} c {{Q'}} →
Q' ⇝ Q →
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P Q Q' c Hhoare Himp.
intros st st' Hc HP.
apply Himp.
apply (Hhoare st st').
assumption. assumption. Qed.
For example, we might use the first consequence rule like this:
{{ True }} =>
{{ 1 = 1 }}
X ::= 1
{{ X = 1 }}
Or, formally...
{{ 1 = 1 }}
X ::= 1
{{ X = 1 }}
Example hoare_asgn_example1 :
{{fun st => True}} (X ::= (ANum 1)) {{fun st => st X = 1}}.
Proof.
apply hoare_consequence_pre
with (P' := assn_sub X (ANum 1) (fun st => st X = 1)).
apply hoare_asgn.
intros st H. reflexivity. Qed.
Finally, for convenience in some proofs, we can state a "combined"
rule of consequence that allows us to vary both the precondition
and the postcondition.
{{P'}} c {{Q'}} | |
P ⇝ P' | |
Q' ⇝ Q | (hoare_consequence) |
{{P}} c {{Q}} |
Theorem hoare_consequence : ∀(P P' Q Q' : Assertion) c,
{{P'}} c {{Q'}} →
P ⇝ P' →
Q' ⇝ Q →
{{P}} c {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P P' Q Q' c Hht HPP' HQ'Q.
intros st st' Hc HP.
apply HQ'Q. apply (Hht st st'). assumption.
apply HPP'. assumption. Qed.
Digression: The eapply Tactic
Example hoare_asgn_example1' :
{{fun st => True}}
(X ::= (ANum 1))
{{fun st => st X = 1}}.
Proof.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn.
intros st H. reflexivity. Qed.
In general, eapply H tactic works just like apply H
except that, instead of failing if unifying the goal with the
conclusion of H does not determine how to instantiate all
of the variables appearing in the premises of H, eapply H
will replace these variables with existential variables
(written ?nnn) as placeholders for expressions that will be
determined (by further unification) later in the proof.
In order for Qed to succeed, all existential variables need to
be determined by the end of the proof. Otherwise Coq will
(rightfully) refuse to accept the proof. Remember that the Coq
tactics build proof objects, and proof objects containing
existential variables are not complete.
Lemma silly1 : ∀(P : nat → nat → Prop) (Q : nat → Prop),
(∀x y : nat, P x y) →
(∀x y : nat, P x y → Q x) →
Q 42.
Proof.
intros P Q HP HQ. eapply HQ. apply HP. Admitted.
Coq gives a warning after apply HP:
An additional constraint is that existential variables cannot be
instantiated with terms containing (normal) variables that did not
exist at the time the existential variable was created.
No more subgoals but non-instantiated existential variables:
Existential 1 =
?171 : [P : nat → nat → Prop
Q : nat → Prop
HP : ∀ x y : nat, P x y
HQ : ∀ x y : nat, P x y → Q x ⊢ nat]
Trying to finish the proof with Qed instead of Admitted gives
an error:
Existential 1 =
?171 : [P : nat → nat → Prop
Q : nat → Prop
HP : ∀ x y : nat, P x y
HQ : ∀ x y : nat, P x y → Q x ⊢ nat]
Error: Attempt to save a proof with existential variables still non-instantiated
Lemma silly2 : ∀(P : nat → nat → Prop) (Q : nat → Prop),
(∃y, P 42 y) →
(∀x y : nat, P x y → Q x) →
Q 42.
Proof.
intros P Q HP HQ. eapply HQ. destruct HP as [y HP']. Admitted.
Doing apply HP' above fails with the following error:
Error: Impossible to unify "?175" with "y".
In this case there is an easy fix:
doing destruct HP before doing eapply HQ.
Lemma silly2_fixed : ∀(P : nat → nat → Prop) (Q : nat → Prop),
(∃y, P 42 y) →
(∀x y : nat, P x y → Q x) →
Q 42.
Proof.
intros P Q HP HQ. destruct HP as [y HP']. eapply HQ. apply HP'.
Qed.
In the last step we did apply HP' which unifies the existential
variable in the goal with the variable y. The assumption
tactic doesn't work in this case, since it cannot handle
existential variables. However, Coq also provides an eassumption
tactic that solves the goal if one of the premises matches the
goal up to instantiations of existential variables. We can use
it instead of apply HP'.
Lemma silly2_eassumption : ∀(P : nat → nat → Prop) (Q : nat → Prop),
(∃y, P 42 y) →
(∀x y : nat, P x y → Q x) →
Q 42.
Proof.
intros P Q HP HQ. destruct HP as [y HP']. eapply HQ. eassumption.
Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_asgn_examples_2)
Translate these informal Hoare triples...
{{ X + 1 <= 5 }} X ::= X + 1 {{ X <= 5 }}
{{ 0 <= 3 ∧ 3 <= 5 }} X ::= 3 {{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
...into formal statements and use hoare_asgn and
hoare_consequence_pre to prove them.
{{ 0 <= 3 ∧ 3 <= 5 }} X ::= 3 {{ 0 <= X ∧ X <= 5 }}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Skip
(hoare_skip) | |
{{ P }} SKIP {{ P }} |
Theorem hoare_skip : ∀P,
{{P}} SKIP {{P}}.
Proof.
intros P st st' H HP. inversion H. subst.
assumption. Qed.
Sequencing
{{ P }} c1 {{ Q }} | |
{{ Q }} c2 {{ R }} | (hoare_seq) |
{{ P }} c1;c2 {{ R }} |
Theorem hoare_seq : ∀P Q R c1 c2,
{{Q}} c2 {{R}} →
{{P}} c1 {{Q}} →
{{P}} c1;c2 {{R}}.
Proof.
intros P Q R c1 c2 H1 H2 st st' H12 Pre.
inversion H12; subst.
apply (H1 st'0 st'); try assumption.
apply (H2 st st'0); assumption. Qed.
Note that, in the formal rule hoare_seq, the premises are
given in "backwards" order (c2 before c1). This matches the
natural flow of information in many of the situations where we'll
use the rule: the natural way to construct a Hoare-logic proof is
to begin at the end of the program (with the final postcondition)
and push postconditions backwards through commands until we reach
the beginning.
Informally, a nice way of recording a proof using the sequencing
rule is as a "decorated program" where the intermediate assertion
Q is written between c1 and c2:
{{ a = n }}
X ::= a;
{{ X = n }} <---- decoration for Q
SKIP
{{ X = n }}
X ::= a;
{{ X = n }} <---- decoration for Q
SKIP
{{ X = n }}
Example hoare_asgn_example3 : ∀a n,
{{fun st => aeval st a = n}}
(X ::= a; SKIP)
{{fun st => st X = n}}.
Proof.
intros a n. eapply hoare_seq.
Case "right part of seq".
apply hoare_skip.
Case "left part of seq".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
intros st H. subst. reflexivity. Qed.
You will most often use hoare_seq and
hoare_consequence_pre in conjunction with the eapply tactic,
as done above.
Exercise: 2 stars (hoare_asgn_example4)
Translate this decorated program into a formal proof:
{{ True }} =>
{{ 1 = 1 }}
X ::= 1;
{{ X = 1 }} =>
{{ X = 1 ∧ 2 = 2 }}
Y ::= 2
{{ X = 1 ∧ Y = 2 }}
{{ 1 = 1 }}
X ::= 1;
{{ X = 1 }} =>
{{ X = 1 ∧ 2 = 2 }}
Y ::= 2
{{ X = 1 ∧ Y = 2 }}
Example hoare_asgn_example4 :
{{fun st => True}} (X ::= (ANum 1); Y ::= (ANum 2))
{{fun st => st X = 1 ∧ st Y = 2}}.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 3 stars (swap_exercise)
Write an Imp program c that swaps the values of X and Y and show (in Coq) that it satisfies the following specification:
{{X <= Y}} c {{Y <= X}}
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (hoarestate1)
Explain why the following proposition can't be proven:
∀ (a : aexp) (n : nat),
{{fun st => aeval st a = n}} (X ::= (ANum 3); Y ::= a)
{{fun st => st Y = n}}.
{{fun st => aeval st a = n}} (X ::= (ANum 3); Y ::= a)
{{fun st => st Y = n}}.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Conditionals
{{P}} c1 {{Q}} | |
{{P}} c2 {{Q}} | |
{{P}} IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 {{Q}} |
{{True}}
IFB X == 0
THEN Y ::= 2
ELSE Y ::= X + 1
FI
{{ X <= Y }}
since the rule tells us nothing about the state in which the
assignments take place in the "then" and "else" branches.
IFB X == 0
THEN Y ::= 2
ELSE Y ::= X + 1
FI
{{ X <= Y }}
{{P ∧ b}} c1 {{Q}} | |
{{P ∧ ~b}} c2 {{Q}} | (hoare_if) |
{{P}} IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI {{Q}} |
Definition bassn b : Assertion :=
fun st => (beval st b = true).
A couple of useful facts about bassn:
Lemma bexp_eval_true : ∀b st,
beval st b = true → (bassn b) st.
Proof.
intros b st Hbe.
unfold bassn. assumption. Qed.
Lemma bexp_eval_false : ∀b st,
beval st b = false → ~ ((bassn b) st).
Proof.
intros b st Hbe contra.
unfold bassn in contra.
rewrite → contra in Hbe. inversion Hbe. Qed.
Now we can formalize the Hoare proof rule for conditionals
and prove it correct.
Theorem hoare_if : ∀P Q b c1 c2,
{{fun st => P st ∧ bassn b st}} c1 {{Q}} →
{{fun st => P st ∧ ~(bassn b st)}} c2 {{Q}} →
{{P}} (IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P Q b c1 c2 HTrue HFalse st st' HE HP.
inversion HE; subst.
Case "b is true".
apply (HTrue st st').
assumption.
split. assumption.
apply bexp_eval_true. assumption.
Case "b is false".
apply (HFalse st st').
assumption.
split. assumption.
apply bexp_eval_false. assumption. Qed.
Here is a formal proof that the program we used to motivate the
rule satisfies the specification we gave.
Example if_example :
{{fun st => True}}
IFB (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))
THEN (Y ::= (ANum 2))
ELSE (Y ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 1))
FI
{{fun st => st X <= st Y}}.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
apply hoare_if.
Case "Then".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
unfold bassn, assn_sub, update, assert_implies. simpl. intros st [_ H].
symmetry in H; apply beq_nat_eq in H.
rewrite H. omega.
Case "Else".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
unfold assn_sub, update, assert_implies; simpl; intros st _. omega.
Qed.
Exercise: One-sided conditionals
Exercise: 4 stars, recommended (if1_hoare)
Module If1.
Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CAss : id → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com
| CIf1 : bexp → com → com.
Tactic Notation "com_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "SKIP" | Case_aux c "::=" | Case_aux c ";"
| Case_aux c "IFB" | Case_aux c "WHILE" | Case_aux c "CIF1" ].
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "c1 ; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "X '::=' a" :=
(CAss X a) (at level 60).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' e1 'THEN' e2 'ELSE' e3 'FI'" :=
(CIf e1 e2 e3) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IF1' b 'THEN' c 'FI'" :=
(CIf1 b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
We now extend the evaluation relation to accommodate IF1
branches. What rule(s) need to be added to ceval to evaluate
one-sided conditionals?
Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '⇓' st'" (at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive ceval : com → state → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀st : state, SKIP / st ⇓ st
| E_Ass : ∀(st : state) (a1 : aexp) (n : nat) (X : id),
aeval st a1 = n → (X ::= a1) / st ⇓ update st X n
| E_Seq : ∀(c1 c2 : com) (st st' st'' : state),
c1 / st ⇓ st' → c2 / st' ⇓ st'' → (c1 ; c2) / st ⇓ st''
| E_IfTrue : ∀(st st' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 c2 : com),
beval st b1 = true →
c1 / st ⇓ st' → (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇓ st'
| E_IfFalse : ∀(st st' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 c2 : com),
beval st b1 = false →
c2 / st ⇓ st' → (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇓ st'
| E_WhileEnd : ∀(b1 : bexp) (st : state) (c1 : com),
beval st b1 = false → (WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st ⇓ st
| E_WhileLoop : ∀(st st' st'' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 : com),
beval st b1 = true →
c1 / st ⇓ st' →
(WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st' ⇓ st'' →
(WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st ⇓ st''
(* FILL IN HERE *)
where "c1 '/' st '⇓' st'" := (ceval c1 st st').
Tactic Notation "ceval_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "E_Skip" | Case_aux c "E_Ass" | Case_aux c "E_Seq"
| Case_aux c "E_IfTrue" | Case_aux c "E_IfFalse"
| Case_aux c "E_WhileEnd" | Case_aux c "E_WhileLoop"
(* FILL IN HERE *)
].
We repeat the definition and notation of Hoare triples.
Definition hoare_triple (P:Assertion) (c:com) (Q:Assertion) : Prop :=
∀st st',
c / st ⇓ st' →
P st →
Q st'.
Notation "{{ P }} c {{ Q }}" := (hoare_triple P c Q)
(at level 90, c at next level)
: hoare_spec_scope.
Now state and prove a theorem, hoare_if1, that expresses an
appropriate Hoare logic proof rule for one-sided conditionals. Try
to come up with a rule that is both sound and as precise as
possible.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
For full credit, prove formally that your rule is precise enough
to show the following valid Hoare triple:
Hint: Your proof of this triple may need to use the other proof
rules also. Because we're working in a separate module, you'll
need to copy here the rules you find necessary.
{{ X + Y = Z }}
IF1 Y <> 0 THEN
X ::= X + Y
FI
{{ X = Z }}
IF1 Y <> 0 THEN
X ::= X + Y
FI
{{ X = Z }}
Lemma hoare_if1_good :
{{ fun st => st X + st Y = st Z }}
IF1 BNot (BEq (AId Y) (ANum 0)) THEN
X ::= APlus (AId X) (AId Y)
FI
{{ fun st => st X = st Z }}.
Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
End If1.
☐
Loops
WHILE b DO c END
and we want to find a pre-condition P and a post-condition
Q such that
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{Q}}
is a valid triple.
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{P}}.
But, as we remarked above for the conditional, we know a
little more at the end — not just P, but also the fact
that b is false in the current state. So we can enrich the
postcondition a little:
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{P ∧ ~b}}
What about the case where the loop body does get executed?
In order to ensure that P holds when the loop finally
exits, we certainly need to make sure that the command c
guarantees that P holds whenever c is finished.
Moreover, since P holds at the beginning of the first
execution of c, and since each execution of c
re-establishes P when it finishes, we can always assume
that P holds at the beginning of c. This leads us to the
following rule:
{{P}} c {{P}} | |
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{P ∧ ~b}} |
{{P ∧ b}} c {{P}} | (hoare_while) |
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{P ∧ ~b}} |
Lemma hoare_while : ∀P b c,
{{fun st => P st ∧ bassn b st}} c {{P}} →
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{fun st => P st ∧ ~ (bassn b st)}}.
Proof.
intros P b c Hhoare st st' He HP.
(* Like we've seen before, we need to reason by induction
on He, because, in the "keep looping" case, its hypotheses
talk about the whole loop instead of just c *)
remember (WHILE b DO c END) as wcom.
ceval_cases (induction He) Case; try (inversion Heqwcom); subst.
Case "E_WhileEnd".
split. assumption. apply bexp_eval_false. assumption.
Case "E_WhileLoop".
apply IHHe2. reflexivity.
apply (Hhoare st st'). assumption.
split. assumption. apply bexp_eval_true. assumption. Qed.
Example while_example :
{{fun st => st X <= 3}}
WHILE (BLe (AId X) (ANum 2))
DO X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 1) END
{{fun st => st X = 3}}.
Proof.
eapply hoare_consequence_post.
apply hoare_while.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn.
unfold bassn, assn_sub, assert_implies, update. simpl.
intros st [H1 H2]. apply ble_nat_true in H2. omega.
unfold bassn, assert_implies. intros st [Hle Hb].
simpl in Hb. remember (ble_nat (st X) 2) as le. destruct le.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet. apply Hb; reflexivity.
symmetry in Heqle. apply ble_nat_false in Heqle. omega.
Qed.
We can also use the while rule to prove the following Hoare
triple, which may seem surprising at first...
Theorem always_loop_hoare : ∀P Q,
{{P}} WHILE BTrue DO SKIP END {{Q}}.
Proof.
intros P Q.
apply hoare_consequence_pre with (P' := fun st : state => True).
eapply hoare_consequence_post.
apply hoare_while.
Case "Loop body preserves invariant".
apply hoare_post_true. intros st. apply I.
Case "Loop invariant and negated guard imply postcondition".
simpl. intros st [Hinv Hguard].
apply ex_falso_quodlibet. apply Hguard. reflexivity.
Case "Precondition implies invariant".
intros st H. constructor. Qed.
Actually, this result shouldn't be surprising. If we look back at
the definition of hoare_triple, we can see that it asserts
something meaningful only when the command terminates.
Print hoare_triple.
If the command doesn't terminate, we can prove anything we like
about the post-condition. Here's a more direct proof of the same
fact:
Theorem always_loop_hoare' : ∀P Q,
{{P}} WHILE BTrue DO SKIP END {{Q}}.
Proof.
unfold hoare_triple. intros P Q st st' contra.
apply loop_never_stops in contra. inversion contra.
Qed.
Hoare rules that only talk about terminating commands are often
said to describe a logic of "partial" correctness. It is also
possible to give Hoare rules for "total" correctness, which build
in the fact that the commands terminate. However, in this course
we will focus only on partial correctness.
Module RepeatExercise.
Exercise: 4 stars (hoare_repeat)
In this exercise, we'll add a new command to our language of commands: REPEAT c UNTIL a END. You will write the evaluation rule for repeat and add a new Hoare rule to the language for programs involving it.Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CAsgn : id → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com
| CRepeat : com → bexp → com.
REPEAT behaves like WHILE, except that the loop guard is
checked after each execution of the body, with the loop
repeating as long as the guard stays false. Because of this,
the body will always execute at least once.
Tactic Notation "com_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "SKIP" | Case_aux c "::=" | Case_aux c ";"
| Case_aux c "IFB" | Case_aux c "WHILE" | Case_aux c "CRepeat" ].
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "c1 ; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "X '::=' a" :=
(CAsgn X a) (at level 60).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' e1 'THEN' e2 'ELSE' e3 'FI'" :=
(CIf e1 e2 e3) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'REPEAT' e1 'UNTIL' b2 'END'" :=
(CRepeat e1 b2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Add new rules for REPEAT to ceval below. You can use the rules
for WHILE as a guide, but remember that the body of a REPEAT
should always execute at least once, and that the loop ends when
the guard becomes true. Then update the ceval_cases tactic to
handle these added cases.
Inductive ceval : state → com → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀st,
ceval st SKIP st
| E_Ass : ∀st a1 n X,
aeval st a1 = n →
ceval st (X ::= a1) (update st X n)
| E_Seq : ∀c1 c2 st st' st'',
ceval st c1 st' →
ceval st' c2 st'' →
ceval st (c1 ; c2) st''
| E_IfTrue : ∀st st' b1 c1 c2,
beval st b1 = true →
ceval st c1 st' →
ceval st (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) st'
| E_IfFalse : ∀st st' b1 c1 c2,
beval st b1 = false →
ceval st c2 st' →
ceval st (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) st'
| E_WhileEnd : ∀b1 st c1,
beval st b1 = false →
ceval st (WHILE b1 DO c1 END) st
| E_WhileLoop : ∀st st' st'' b1 c1,
beval st b1 = true →
ceval st c1 st' →
ceval st' (WHILE b1 DO c1 END) st'' →
ceval st (WHILE b1 DO c1 END) st''
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Tactic Notation "ceval_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "E_Skip" | Case_aux c "E_Ass" | Case_aux c "E_Seq"
| Case_aux c "E_IfTrue" | Case_aux c "E_IfFalse"
| Case_aux c "E_WhileEnd" | Case_aux c "E_WhileLoop"
(* FILL IN HERE *)
].
A couple of definitions from above, copied here so they use the
new ceval.
Notation "c1 '/' st '⇓' st'" := (ceval st c1 st')
(at level 40, st at level 39).
Definition hoare_triple (P:Assertion) (c:com) (Q:Assertion)
: Prop :=
∀st st', (c / st ⇓ st') → P st → Q st'.
Notation "{{ P }} c {{ Q }}" :=
(hoare_triple P c Q) (at level 90, c at next level).
To make sure you've got the evaluation rules for REPEAT right,
prove that ex1_repeat evaluates correctly.
Definition ex1_repeat :=
REPEAT
X ::= ANum 1;
Y ::= APlus (AId Y) (ANum 1)
UNTIL (BEq (AId X) (ANum 1)) END.
Theorem ex1_repeat_works :
ex1_repeat / empty_state ⇓ update (update empty_state X 1) Y 1.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Now state and prove a theorem, hoare_repeat, that expresses an
appropriate proof rule for repeat commands. Use hoare_while
as a model, and try to make your rule as precise as possible.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
For full credit, make sure (informally) that your rule can be used
to prove the following valid Hoare triple:
{{ X > 0 }}
REPEAT
Y ::= X;
X ::= X - 1
UNTIL X = 0 END
{{ X = 0 ∧ Y > 0 }}
REPEAT
Y ::= X;
X ::= X - 1
UNTIL X = 0 END
{{ X = 0 ∧ Y > 0 }}
End RepeatExercise.
☐
Exercise: HAVOC
Exercise: 3 stars (himp_hoare)
Module Himp.
Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CAsgn : id → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com
| CHavoc : id → com.
Tactic Notation "com_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "SKIP" | Case_aux c "::=" | Case_aux c ";"
| Case_aux c "IFB" | Case_aux c "WHILE" | Case_aux c "HAVOC" ].
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "X '::=' a" :=
(CAsgn X a) (at level 60).
Notation "c1 ; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' e1 'THEN' e2 'ELSE' e3 'FI'" :=
(CIf e1 e2 e3) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'HAVOC' X" := (CHavoc X) (at level 60).
Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '⇓' st'" (at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive ceval : com → state → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀st : state, SKIP / st ⇓ st
| E_Ass : ∀(st : state) (a1 : aexp) (n : nat) (X : id),
aeval st a1 = n → (X ::= a1) / st ⇓ update st X n
| E_Seq : ∀(c1 c2 : com) (st st' st'' : state),
c1 / st ⇓ st' → c2 / st' ⇓ st'' → (c1 ; c2) / st ⇓ st''
| E_IfTrue : ∀(st st' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 c2 : com),
beval st b1 = true →
c1 / st ⇓ st' → (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇓ st'
| E_IfFalse : ∀(st st' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 c2 : com),
beval st b1 = false →
c2 / st ⇓ st' → (IFB b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇓ st'
| E_WhileEnd : ∀(b1 : bexp) (st : state) (c1 : com),
beval st b1 = false → (WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st ⇓ st
| E_WhileLoop : ∀(st st' st'' : state) (b1 : bexp) (c1 : com),
beval st b1 = true →
c1 / st ⇓ st' →
(WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st' ⇓ st'' →
(WHILE b1 DO c1 END) / st ⇓ st''
| E_Havoc : ∀(st : state) (X : id) (n : nat),
(HAVOC X) / st ⇓ update st X n
where "c1 '/' st '⇓' st'" := (ceval c1 st st').
Tactic Notation "ceval_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "E_Skip" | Case_aux c "E_Ass" | Case_aux c "E_Seq"
| Case_aux c "E_IfTrue" | Case_aux c "E_IfFalse"
| Case_aux c "E_WhileEnd" | Case_aux c "E_WhileLoop"
| Case_aux c "E_Havoc" ].
The definition of Hoare triples is exactly as before. Unlike our
notion of equivalence, which had subtle consequences with
occassionally nonterminating commands (exercise havoc_diverge),
this definition is still fully satisfactory. Convince yourself of
this before proceeding.
Definition hoare_triple (P:Assertion) (c:com) (Q:Assertion) : Prop :=
∀st st', c / st ⇓ st' → P st → Q st'.
Notation "{{ P }} c {{ Q }}" := (hoare_triple P c Q)
(at level 90, c at next level)
: hoare_spec_scope.
Complete the Hoare rule for HAVOC commands below by defining
havoc_pre and prove that the resulting rule is correct.
Definition havoc_pre (X : id) (Q : Assertion) : Assertion :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Theorem hoare_havoc : ∀(Q : Assertion) (X : id),
{{ havoc_pre X Q }} HAVOC X {{ Q }}.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Like in the hoare_asgn_weakest exercise above, show that your
havoc_pre returns the weakest precondition.
Lemma hoare_havoc_weakest : ∀(P Q : Assertion) (X : id),
{{ P }} HAVOC X {{ Q }} →
P ⇝ havoc_pre X Q.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(* /SOLUTION *)
End Himp.
☐
Review of Hoare Logic
(hoare_asgn) | |
{{assn_sub X a Q}} X::=a {{Q}} |
(hoare_skip) | |
{{ P }} SKIP {{ P }} |
{{ P }} c1 {{ Q }} | |
{{ Q }} c2 {{ R }} | (hoare_seq) |
{{ P }} c1;c2 {{ R }} |
{{P ∧ b}} c1 {{Q}} | |
{{P ∧ ~b}} c2 {{Q}} | (hoare_if) |
{{P}} IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI {{Q}} |
{{P ∧ b}} c {{P}} | (hoare_while) |
{{P}} WHILE b DO c END {{P ∧ ~b}} |
{{P'}} c {{Q'}} | |
P ⇝ P' | |
Q' ⇝ Q | (hoare_consequence) |
{{P}} c {{Q}} |
Decorated Programs
{{ True }} =>
{{ x = x }}
X ::= x;
{{ X = x }} =>
{{ X = x ∧ z = z }}
Z ::= z;
{{ X = x ∧ Z = z }} =>
{{ Z - X = z - x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ Z - X = z - x ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
{{ (Z - 1) - (X - 1) = z - x }}
Z ::= Z - 1;
{{ Z - (X - 1) = z - x }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Z - X = z - x }}
END;
{{ Z - X = z - x ∧ ~ (X <> 0) }} =>
{{ Z = z - x }} =>
{{ Z + 1 = z - x + 1 }}
Z ::= Z + 1
{{ Z = z - x + 1 }}
{{ x = x }}
X ::= x;
{{ X = x }} =>
{{ X = x ∧ z = z }}
Z ::= z;
{{ X = x ∧ Z = z }} =>
{{ Z - X = z - x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ Z - X = z - x ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
{{ (Z - 1) - (X - 1) = z - x }}
Z ::= Z - 1;
{{ Z - (X - 1) = z - x }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Z - X = z - x }}
END;
{{ Z - X = z - x ∧ ~ (X <> 0) }} =>
{{ Z = z - x }} =>
{{ Z + 1 = z - x + 1 }}
Z ::= Z + 1
{{ Z = z - x + 1 }}
- SKIP is locally consistent if its precondition and
postcondition are the same:
{{ P }}
SKIP
{{ P }} - The sequential composition of commands c1 and c2 is locally
consistent (with respect to assertions P and R) if c1 is
locally consistent (with respect to P and Q) and c2 is
locally consistent (with respect to Q and R):
{{ P }}
c1;
{{ Q }}
c2
{{ R }} - An assignment is locally consistent if its precondition is
the appropriate substitution of its postcondition:
{{ P where a is substituted for X }}
X ::= a
{{ P }} - A conditional is locally consistent (with respect to assertions
P and Q) if the assertions at the top of its "then" and
"else" branches are exactly P∧b and P/\~b and if its "then"
branch is locally consistent (with respect to P∧b and Q)
and its "else" branch is locally consistent (with respect to
P/\~b and Q):
{{ P }}
IFB b THEN
{{ P ∧ b }}
c1
{{ Q }}
ELSE
{{ P ∧ ~b }}
c2
{{ Q }}
FI
{{ Q }} - A while loop is locally consistent if its postcondition is
P/\~b (where P is its precondition) and if the pre- and
postconditions of its body are exactly P∧b and P:
{{ P }}
WHILE b DO
{{ P ∧ b }}
c1
{{ P }}
END
{{ P ∧ ~b }} - A pair of assertions separated by => is locally consistent if
the first implies the second (in all states):
{{ P }} =>
{{ P' }}
Example: Slow Subtraction
(1) {{ X = x ∧ Z = z }} =>
(2) {{ Z - X = z - x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
(3) {{ Z - X = z - x ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
(4) {{ (Z - 1) - (X - 1) = z - x }}
Z ::= Z - 1;
(5) {{ Z - (X - 1) = z - x }}
X ::= X - 1
(6) {{ Z - X = z - x }}
END
(7) {{ Z - X = z - x ∧ ~ (X <> 0) }} =>
(8) {{ Z = z - x }}
The decorations were constructed as follows:
(2) {{ Z - X = z - x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
(3) {{ Z - X = z - x ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
(4) {{ (Z - 1) - (X - 1) = z - x }}
Z ::= Z - 1;
(5) {{ Z - (X - 1) = z - x }}
X ::= X - 1
(6) {{ Z - X = z - x }}
END
(7) {{ Z - X = z - x ∧ ~ (X <> 0) }} =>
(8) {{ Z = z - x }}
- Begin with the undecorated program (the unnumbered lines).
- Add the specification — i.e., the outer precondition (1) and postcondition (8).
- Write down the invariant of the loop (6).
- Following the format dictated by the hoare_while rule, add the final use of the rule of consequence — the assertion in line (7) and the check that (7) implies (8).
- Check that the loop invariant is an invariant of the loop body by using the assignment rule twice to push the invariant backwards from the end of the loop body to the beginning (line (5) and then line (4)), and then filling in the rule of consequence asserting that the invariant plus the fact that the loop guard is true (line (3)) implies line (4).
- Check that the invariant is established at the beginning of the loop verifying that line (2) is implied by line (1).
Definition subtract_slowly : com :=
WHILE BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0)) DO
Z ::= AMinus (AId Z) (ANum 1);
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)
END.
Definition subtract_slowly_invariant x z :=
fun st => minus (st Z) (st X) = minus z x.
Theorem subtract_slowly_correct : ∀x z,
{{fun st => st X = x ∧ st Z = z}}
subtract_slowly
{{fun st => st Z = minus z x}}.
Proof.
(* Note that we do NOT unfold the definition of hoare_triple
anywhere in this proof! The goal is to use only the Hoare
rules. Your proofs should do the same. *)
intros x z. unfold subtract_slowly.
(* First we need to transform the pre and postconditions so
that hoare_while will apply. In particular, the
precondition should be the loop invariant. *)
eapply hoare_consequence with (P' := subtract_slowly_invariant x z).
apply hoare_while.
Case "Loop body preserves invariant".
(* Split up the two assignments with hoare_seq - using eapply
lets us solve the second one immediately with hoare_asgn *)
eapply hoare_seq. apply hoare_asgn.
(* Now for the first assignment, transform the precondition
so we can use hoare_asgn *)
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
(* Finally, we need to justify the implication generated by
hoare_consequence_pre (this bit of reasoning is elided in the
informal proof) *)
unfold subtract_slowly_invariant, assn_sub, update, bassn. simpl.
intros st [Inv GuardTrue].
(* Could alternatively do case analysis on
negb (beq_nat (st X) 0) here;
but SearchAbout reveals some nice lemmas *)
SearchAbout [negb true]. rewrite negb_true_iff in GuardTrue.
SearchAbout [beq_nat false]. apply beq_nat_false in GuardTrue.
omega. (* slow but effective! *)
(* Faster variant: rewrite <- Inv. clear Inv. omega. *)
Case "Initial state satisfies invariant".
(* This is the subgoal generated by the precondition part of our
first use of hoare_consequence. It's the first implication
written in the decorated program (though we elided the actual
proof there). *)
unfold subtract_slowly_invariant.
intros st [HX HZ]. omega.
Case "Invariant and negated guard imply postcondition".
(* This is the subgoal generated by the postcondition part of
out first use of hoare_consequence. This implication is
the one written after the while loop in the informal proof. *)
intros st [Inv GuardFalse].
unfold subtract_slowly_invariant in Inv.
unfold bassn in GuardFalse. simpl in GuardFalse.
(* SearchAbout helps again to find the right lemmas *)
SearchAbout [not true]. rewrite not_true_iff_false in GuardFalse.
SearchAbout [negb false]. rewrite negb_false_iff in GuardFalse.
SearchAbout [beq_nat true]. apply beq_nat_true in GuardFalse.
omega. Qed.
Exercise: Reduce to Zero
Exercise: 2 stars (reduce_to_zero_correct)
Here is a while loop that is so simple it needs no invariant:
{{ True }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ True ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
{{ True }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ True }}
END
{{ True ∧ X = 0 }} =>
{{ X = 0 }}
Your job is to translate this proof to Coq. Refer to the
slow_subtraction example for ideas.
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ True ∧ X <> 0 }} =>
{{ True }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ True }}
END
{{ True ∧ X = 0 }} =>
{{ X = 0 }}
Definition reduce_to_zero : com :=
WHILE BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0)) DO
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)
END.
Theorem reduce_to_zero_correct :
{{fun st => True}}
reduce_to_zero
{{fun st => st X = 0}}.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: Slow Addition
Definition add_slowly : com :=
WHILE BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0)) DO
Z ::= APlus (AId Z) (ANum 1);
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)
END.
Exercise: 3 stars (add_slowly_decoration)
Following the pattern of the subtract_slowly example above, pick a precondition and postcondition that give an appropriate specification of add_slowly; then (informally) decorate the program accordingly.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 3 stars (add_slowly_formal)
Now write down your specification of add_slowly formally, as a Coq Hoare_triple, and prove it valid.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Example: Parity
{{ X = x }} =>
{{ X = x ∧ 0 = 0 }}
Y ::= 0;
{{ X = x ∧ Y = 0 }} =>
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x ∧ X<>0 }} =>
{{ (1-Y)=0 ↔ ev (x-(X-1)) ∧ X-1<=x }}
Y ::= 1 - Y;
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev (x-(X-1)) ∧ X-1<=x }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X) ∧ X<=x }}
END
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x ∧ ~(X<>0) }} =>
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev x }}
{{ X = x ∧ 0 = 0 }}
Y ::= 0;
{{ X = x ∧ Y = 0 }} =>
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x }}
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x ∧ X<>0 }} =>
{{ (1-Y)=0 ↔ ev (x-(X-1)) ∧ X-1<=x }}
Y ::= 1 - Y;
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev (x-(X-1)) ∧ X-1<=x }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X) ∧ X<=x }}
END
{{ (Y=0 ↔ ev (x-X)) ∧ X<=x ∧ ~(X<>0) }} =>
{{ Y=0 ↔ ev x }}
Definition find_parity : com :=
Y ::= (ANum 0);
WHILE (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) DO
Y ::= AMinus (ANum 1) (AId Y);
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)
END.
Definition find_parity_invariant x :=
fun st =>
st X <= x ∧ ((st Y = 0 ∧ ev (x - st X))
∨ (st Y = 1 ∧ ~ev (x - st X))).
We'll need the following lemma...
Lemma not_ev_ev_S_gen: ∀n,
(~ ev n → ev (S n)) ∧
(~ ev (S n) → ev (S (S n))).
Proof.
induction n as [| n'].
Case "n = 0".
split; intros H.
SCase "→".
apply ex_falso_quodlibet. apply H. apply ev_0.
SCase "←".
apply ev_SS. apply ev_0.
Case "n = S n'".
inversion IHn' as [Hn HSn]. split; intros H.
SCase "→".
apply HSn. apply H.
SCase "←".
apply ev_SS. apply Hn. intros contra.
apply H. apply ev_SS. apply contra. Qed.
Lemma not_ev_ev_S : ∀n,
~ ev n → ev (S n).
Proof.
intros n.
destruct (not_ev_ev_S_gen n) as [H _].
apply H.
Qed.
Theorem find_parity_correct : ∀x,
{{fun st => st X = x}}
find_parity
{{fun st => st Y = 0 ↔ ev x}}.
Proof.
intros x. unfold find_parity.
apply hoare_seq with (Q := find_parity_invariant x).
eapply hoare_consequence.
apply hoare_while with (P := find_parity_invariant x).
Case "Loop body preserves invariant".
eapply hoare_seq.
apply hoare_asgn.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn.
intros st [[Inv1 Inv2] GuardTrue].
unfold find_parity_invariant, bassn, assn_sub, aeval in *.
rewrite update_eq.
rewrite (update_neq Y X).
rewrite (update_neq X Y).
rewrite update_eq.
simpl in GuardTrue. destruct (st X).
inversion GuardTrue. simpl.
split. omega.
inversion Inv2 as [[H1 H2] | [H1 H2]]; rewrite H1;
[right|left]; (split; simpl; [omega |]).
apply ev_not_ev_S in H2.
replace (S (x - S n)) with (x-n) in H2 by omega.
rewrite ← minus_n_O. assumption.
apply not_ev_ev_S in H2.
replace (S (x - S n)) with (x - n) in H2 by omega.
rewrite ← minus_n_O. assumption.
reflexivity. reflexivity.
Case "Precondition implies invariant".
intros st H. assumption.
Case "Invariant implies postcondition".
unfold bassn, find_parity_invariant. simpl.
intros st [[Inv1 Inv2] GuardFalse].
destruct (st X).
split; intro.
inversion Inv2.
inversion H0 as [_ H1]. replace (x-0) with x in H1 by omega.
assumption.
inversion H0 as [H0' _]. rewrite H in H0'. inversion H0'.
inversion Inv2.
inversion H0. assumption.
inversion H0 as [_ H1]. replace (x-0) with x in H1 by omega.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet. apply H1. assumption.
apply ex_falso_quodlibet. apply GuardFalse. reflexivity.
Case "invariant established before loop".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn.
intros st H.
unfold assn_sub, find_parity_invariant, update. simpl.
subst.
split.
omega.
replace (st X - st X) with 0 by omega.
left. split. reflexivity.
apply ev_0. Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars (wrong_find_parity_invariant)
A plausible first attempt at stating an invariant for find_parity is the following.Definition find_parity_invariant' x :=
fun st =>
(st Y) = 0 ↔ ev (x - st X).
Why doesn't this work? (Hint: Don't waste time trying to answer
this exercise by attempting a formal proof and seeing where it
goes wrong. Just think about whether the loop body actually
preserves the property.)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Definition sqrt_loop : com :=
WHILE BLe (AMult (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))
(APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z)))
(AId X) DO
Z ::= APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z)
END.
Definition sqrt_com : com :=
Z ::= ANum 0;
sqrt_loop.
Definition sqrt_spec (x : nat) : Assertion :=
fun st =>
((st Z) * (st Z)) <= x
∧ ~ (((S (st Z)) * (S (st Z))) <= x).
Definition sqrt_inv (x : nat) : Assertion :=
fun st =>
st X = x
∧ ((st Z) * (st Z)) <= x.
Theorem random_fact_1 : ∀st,
(S (st Z)) * (S (st Z)) <= st X →
bassn (BLe (AMult (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))
(APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z)))
(AId X)) st.
Proof.
intros st Hle. unfold bassn. simpl.
destruct (st X) as [|x'].
Case "st X = 0".
inversion Hle.
Case "st X = S x'".
simpl in Hle. apply le_S_n in Hle.
remember (ble_nat (plus (st Z)
((st Z) * (S (st Z)))) x')
as ble.
destruct ble. reflexivity.
symmetry in Heqble. apply ble_nat_false in Heqble.
unfold not in Heqble. apply Heqble in Hle. inversion Hle.
Qed.
Theorem random_fact_2 : ∀st,
bassn (BLe (AMult (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))
(APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z)))
(AId X)) st →
aeval st (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))
* aeval st (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))
<= st X.
Proof.
intros st Hble. unfold bassn in Hble. simpl in *.
destruct (st X) as [| x'].
Case "st X = 0".
inversion Hble.
Case "st X = S x'".
apply ble_nat_true in Hble. omega. Qed.
Theorem sqrt_com_correct : ∀x,
{{fun st => True}} (X ::= ANum x; sqrt_com) {{sqrt_spec x}}.
Proof.
intros x.
apply hoare_seq with (Q := fun st => st X = x).
Case "sqrt_com".
unfold sqrt_com.
apply hoare_seq with (Q := fun st => st X = x
∧ st Z = 0).
SCase "sqrt_loop".
unfold sqrt_loop.
eapply hoare_consequence.
apply hoare_while with (P := sqrt_inv x).
SSCase "loop preserves invariant".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn. intros st H.
unfold assn_sub. unfold sqrt_inv in *.
inversion H as [[HX HZ] HP]. split.
SSSCase "X is preserved".
rewrite update_neq; try assumption; try reflexivity.
SSSCase "Z is updated correctly".
rewrite (update_eq (aeval st (APlus (ANum 1) (AId Z))) Z st).
subst. apply random_fact_2. assumption.
SSCase "invariant is true initially".
intros st H. inversion H as [HX HZ].
unfold sqrt_inv. split. assumption.
rewrite HZ. simpl. omega.
SSCase "after loop, spec is satisfied".
intros st H. unfold sqrt_spec.
inversion H as [HX HP].
unfold sqrt_inv in HX. inversion HX as [HX' Harith].
split. assumption.
intros contra. apply HP. clear HP.
simpl. simpl in contra.
apply random_fact_1. subst x. assumption.
SCase "Z set to 0".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
intros st HX.
unfold assn_sub. split.
rewrite update_neq. assumption. reflexivity.
rewrite update_eq. reflexivity.
Case "assignment of X".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply hoare_asgn.
intros st H.
unfold assn_sub. rewrite update_eq. reflexivity. Qed.
Exercise: 3 stars (sqrt_informal)
Write an informal decorated program corresponding to this formal correctness proof.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Module Factorial.
Recall the mathematical factorial function...
Fixpoint real_fact (n:nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => 1
| S n' => n * (real_fact n')
end.
... and the Imp program that we wrote to calculate factorials:
Definition fact_body : com :=
Y ::= AMult (AId Y) (AId Z);
Z ::= AMinus (AId Z) (ANum 1).
Definition fact_loop : com :=
WHILE BNot (BEq (AId Z) (ANum 0)) DO
fact_body
END.
Definition fact_com : com :=
Z ::= (AId X);
Y ::= ANum 1;
fact_loop.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (fact_informal)
Decorate the fact_com program to show that it satisfies the specification given by the pre and postconditions below. As usual, feel free to elide the algebraic reasoning about arithmetic, the less-than relation, etc., that is formally required by the rule of consequence:
{{ X = x }}
Z ::= X;
Y ::= 1;
WHILE Z <> 0 DO
Y ::= Y * Z;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
{{ Y = real_fact x }}
☐
Z ::= X;
Y ::= 1;
WHILE Z <> 0 DO
Y ::= Y * Z;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
{{ Y = real_fact x }}
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (fact_formal)
Prove formally that fact_com satisfies this specification, using your informal proof as a guide. You may want to state the loop invariant separately (as we did in the examples).Theorem fact_com_correct : ∀x,
{{fun st => st X = x}} fact_com
{{fun st => st Y = real_fact x}}.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
End Factorial.
Formalizing Decorated Programs (Optional)
Syntax
Inductive dcom : Type :=
| DCSkip : Assertion → dcom
| DCSeq : dcom → dcom → dcom
| DCAsgn : id → aexp → Assertion → dcom
| DCIf : bexp → Assertion → dcom → Assertion → dcom
→ Assertion→ dcom
| DCWhile : bexp → Assertion → dcom → Assertion → dcom
| DCPre : Assertion → dcom → dcom
| DCPost : dcom → Assertion → dcom.
Tactic Notation "dcom_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "Skip" | Case_aux c "Seq" | Case_aux c "Asgn"
| Case_aux c "If" | Case_aux c "While"
| Case_aux c "Pre" | Case_aux c "Post" ].
Notation "'SKIP' {{ P }}"
:= (DCSkip P)
(at level 10) : dcom_scope.
Notation "l '::=' a {{ P }}"
:= (DCAsgn l a P)
(at level 60, a at next level) : dcom_scope.
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' {{ Pbody }} d 'END' {{ Ppost }}"
:= (DCWhile b Pbody d Ppost)
(at level 80, right associativity) : dcom_scope.
Notation "'IFB' b 'THEN' {{ P }} d 'ELSE' {{ P' }} d' 'FI' {{ Q }}"
:= (DCIf b P d P' d' Q)
(at level 80, right associativity) : dcom_scope.
Notation "'=>' {{ P }} d"
:= (DCPre P d)
(at level 90, right associativity) : dcom_scope.
Notation "{{ P }} d"
:= (DCPre P d)
(at level 90) : dcom_scope.
Notation "d '=>' {{ P }}"
:= (DCPost d P)
(at level 91, right associativity) : dcom_scope.
Notation " d ; d' "
:= (DCSeq d d')
(at level 80, right associativity) : dcom_scope.
Delimit Scope dcom_scope with dcom.
To avoid clashing with the existing Notation definitions
for ordinary commands, we introduce these notations in a special
scope called dcom_scope, and we wrap examples with the
declaration % dcom to signal that we want the notations to be
interpreted in this scope.
Careful readers will note that we've defined two notations for the
DCPre constructor, one with and one without a =>. The
"without" version is intended to be used to supply the initial
precondition at the very top of the program.
Example dec_while : dcom := (
{{ fun st => True }}
WHILE (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0)))
DO
{{ fun st => True ∧ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st}}
X ::= (AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1))
{{ fun _ => True }}
END
{{ fun st => True ∧ ~bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st}} =>
{{ fun st => st X = 0 }}
) % dcom.
It is easy to go from a dcom to a com by erasing all
annotations.
Fixpoint extract (d:dcom) : com :=
match d with
| DCSkip _ => SKIP
| DCSeq d1 d2 => (extract d1 ; extract d2)
| DCAsgn X a _ => X ::= a
| DCIf b _ d1 _ d2 _ => IFB b THEN extract d1 ELSE extract d2 FI
| DCWhile b _ d _ => WHILE b DO extract d END
| DCPre _ d => extract d
| DCPost d _ => extract d
end.
The choice of exactly where to put assertions in the definition of
dcom is a bit subtle. The simplest thing to do would be to
annotate every dcom with a precondition and postcondition. But
this would result in very verbose programs with a lot of repeated
annotations: for example, a program like SKIP;SKIP would have to
be annotated as
Instead, the rule we've followed is this:
In other words, the invariant of the representation is that a
dcom d together with a precondition P determines a Hoare
triple {{P}} (extract d) {{post d}}, where post is defined as
follows:
{{P}} ({{P}} SKIP {{P}}) ; ({{P}} SKIP {{P}}) {{P}},
with pre- and post-conditions on each SKIP, plus identical pre-
and post-conditions on the semicolon!
- The post-condition expected by each dcom d is embedded in d
- The pre-condition is supplied by the context.
Fixpoint post (d:dcom) : Assertion :=
match d with
| DCSkip P => P
| DCSeq d1 d2 => post d2
| DCAsgn X a Q => Q
| DCIf _ _ d1 _ d2 Q => Q
| DCWhile b Pbody c Ppost => Ppost
| DCPre _ d => post d
| DCPost c Q => Q
end.
We can define a similar function that extracts the "initial
precondition" from a decorated program.
Fixpoint pre (d:dcom) : Assertion :=
match d with
| DCSkip P => fun st => True
| DCSeq c1 c2 => pre c1
| DCAsgn X a Q => fun st => True
| DCIf _ _ t _ e _ => fun st => True
| DCWhile b Pbody c Ppost => fun st => True
| DCPre P c => P
| DCPost c Q => pre c
end.
This function is not doing anything sophisticated like calculating
a weakest precondition; it just recursively searches for an
explicit annotation at the very beginning of the program,
returning default answers for programs that lack an explicit
precondition (like a bare assignment or SKIP).
Using pre and post, and assuming that we adopt the convention
of always supplying an explicit precondition annotation at the
very beginning of our decorated programs, we can express what it
means for a decorated program to be correct as follows:
Definition dec_correct (d:dcom) :=
{{pre d}} (extract d) {{post d}}.
To check whether this Hoare triple is valid, we need a way to
extract the "proof obligations" from a decorated program. These
obligations are often called verification conditions, because
they are the facts that must be verified to see that the
decorations are logically consistent and thus add up to a complete
proof of correctness.
The function verification_conditions takes a dcom d together
with a precondition P and returns a proposition that, if it
can be proved, implies that the triple {{P}} (extract d) {{post d}}
is valid. It does this by walking over d and generating a big
conjunction including all the "local checks" that we listed when
we described the informal rules for decorated programs.
(Strictly speaking, we need to massage the informal rules a little
bit to add some uses of the rule of consequence, but the
correspondence should be clear.)
Extracting Verification Conditions
Fixpoint verification_conditions (P : Assertion) (d:dcom) : Prop :=
match d with
| DCSkip Q =>
(P ⇝ Q)
| DCSeq d1 d2 =>
verification_conditions P d1
∧ verification_conditions (post d1) d2
| DCAsgn X a Q =>
(P ⇝ assn_sub X a Q)
| DCIf b P1 d1 P2 d2 Q =>
((fun st => P st ∧ bassn b st) ⇝ P1)
∧ ((fun st => P st ∧ ~ (bassn b st)) ⇝ P2)
∧ (Q = post d1) ∧ (Q = post d2)
∧ verification_conditions P1 d1
∧ verification_conditions P2 d2
| DCWhile b Pbody d Ppost =>
(* post d is the loop invariant and the initial precondition *)
(P ⇝ post d)
∧ (Pbody = (fun st => post d st ∧ bassn b st))
∧ (Ppost = (fun st => post d st ∧ ~(bassn b st)))
∧ verification_conditions Pbody d
| DCPre P' d =>
(P ⇝ P') ∧ verification_conditions P' d
| DCPost d Q =>
verification_conditions P d ∧ (post d ⇝ Q)
end.
And now, the key theorem, which captures the claim that the
verification_conditions function does its job correctly. Not
surprisingly, we need all of the Hoare Logic rules in the
proof. We have used in variants of several tactics before to
apply them to values in the context rather than the goal. An
extension of this idea is the syntax tactic in *, which applies
tactic in the goal and every hypothesis in the context. We most
commonly use this facility in conjunction with the simpl tactic,
as below.
Theorem verification_correct : ∀d P,
verification_conditions P d → {{P}} (extract d) {{post d}}.
Proof.
dcom_cases (induction d) Case; intros P H; simpl in *.
Case "Skip".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_skip.
assumption.
Case "Seq".
inversion H as [H1 H2]. clear H.
eapply hoare_seq.
apply IHd2. apply H2.
apply IHd1. apply H1.
Case "Asgn".
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_asgn.
assumption.
Case "If".
inversion H as [HPre1 [HPre2 [Hd1 [Hd2 [HThen HElse]]]]]; clear H.
subst.
apply hoare_if.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply IHd1. eassumption. assumption.
rewrite Hd2.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply IHd2. eassumption. assumption.
Case "While".
inversion H as [Hpre [Hbody [Hpost Hd]]]; subst; clear H.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre.
apply hoare_while with (P := post d).
apply IHd. apply Hd.
assumption.
Case "Pre".
inversion H as [HP Hd]; clear H.
eapply hoare_consequence_pre. apply IHd. apply Hd. assumption.
Case "Post".
inversion H as [Hd HQ]; clear H.
eapply hoare_consequence_post. apply IHd. apply Hd. assumption.
Qed.
Examples
Eval simpl in (verification_conditions (fun st => True) dec_while).
(* ====>
= (((fun _ : state => True) ~~> (fun _ : state => True)) /\
((fun _ : state => True) ~~> (fun _ : state => True)) /\
(fun st : state => True /\ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) =
(fun st : state => True /\ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) /\
(fun st : state => True /\ ~ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) =
(fun st : state => True /\ ~ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) /\
(fun st : state => True /\ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) ~~>
assn_sub X (AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)) (fun _ : state => True)) /\
(fun st : state => True /\ ~ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st) ~~>
(fun st : state => st X = 0) *)
We can certainly work with them using just the tactics we have so
far, but we can make things much smoother with a bit of
automation. We first define a custom verify tactic that applies
splitting repeatedly to turn all the conjunctions into separate
subgoals and then uses omega and eauto (a handy
general-purpose automation tactic that we'll discuss in detail
later) to deal with as many of them as possible.
Tactic Notation "verify" :=
apply verification_correct;
repeat split;
simpl; unfold assert_implies;
unfold bassn in *; unfold beval in *; unfold aeval in *;
unfold assn_sub; intros;
repeat rewrite update_eq;
repeat (rewrite update_neq; [| reflexivity]);
simpl in *;
repeat match goal with [H : _ ∧ _ ⊢ _] => destruct H end;
repeat rewrite not_true_iff_false in *;
repeat rewrite not_false_iff_true in *;
repeat rewrite negb_true_iff in *;
repeat rewrite negb_false_iff in *;
repeat rewrite beq_nat_true_iff in *;
repeat rewrite beq_nat_false_iff in *;
try eauto; try omega.
What's left after verify does its thing is "just the interesting
parts" of checking that the decorations are correct. For very
simple examples verify immediately solves the goal (provided
that the annotations are correct).
Theorem dec_while_correct :
dec_correct dec_while.
Proof. verify. Qed.
Another example (formalizing a decorated program we've seen
before):
Example subtract_slowly_dec (x:nat) (z:nat) : dcom := (
{{ fun st => st X = x ∧ st Z = z }}
WHILE BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))
DO {{ fun st => st Z - st X = z - x
∧ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st }}
Z ::= AMinus (AId Z) (ANum 1)
{{ fun st => st Z - (st X - 1) = z - x }} ;
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum 1)
{{ fun st => st Z - st X = z - x }}
END
{{ fun st => st Z
- st X
= z - x
∧ ~ bassn (BNot (BEq (AId X) (ANum 0))) st }}
=>
{{ fun st => st Z = z - x }}
) % dcom.
Theorem subtract_slowly_dec_correct : ∀x z,
dec_correct (subtract_slowly_dec x z).
Proof. intros x z. verify. (* this grinds for a bit! *) Qed.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (slow_assignment_dec)
{{ True }}
X ::= x
{{ X = x }} ;
Y ::= 0
{{ X = x ∧ Y = 0 }} ;
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ X + Y = x ∧ X > 0 }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Y + X + 1 = x }} ;
Y ::= Y + 1
{{ Y + X = x }}
END
{{ Y = x ∧ X = 0 }}
X ::= x
{{ X = x }} ;
Y ::= 0
{{ X = x ∧ Y = 0 }} ;
WHILE X <> 0 DO
{{ X + Y = x ∧ X > 0 }}
X ::= X - 1
{{ Y + X + 1 = x }} ;
Y ::= Y + 1
{{ Y + X = x }}
END
{{ Y = x ∧ X = 0 }}
Example slow_assignment_dec (x:nat) : dcom :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Theorem slow_assignment_dec_correct : ∀x,
dec_correct (slow_assignment_dec x).
Proof. (* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (factorial_dec)
Remember the factorial function we worked with before:Fixpoint real_fact (n:nat) : nat :=
match n with
| O => 1
| S n' => n * (real_fact n')
end.
Following the pattern of subtract_slowly_dec, write a decorated
Imp program that implements the factorial function, and prove it
correct.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Definition div_mod_dec (a b : nat) : dcom := (
{{ fun st => True }} =>
{{ fun st => b * 0 + a = a }}
X ::= ANum a
{{ fun st => b * 0 + st X = a }};
Y ::= ANum 0
{{ fun st => b * st Y + st X = a }};
WHILE (BLe (ANum b) (AId X)) DO
{{ fun st => b * st Y + st X = a ∧ (bassn (BLe (ANum b) (AId X)) st) }} =>
{{ fun st => b * (st Y + 1) + (st X - b) = a }}
X ::= AMinus (AId X) (ANum b)
{{ fun st => b * (st Y + 1) + st X = a }};
Y ::= APlus (AId Y) (ANum 1)
{{ fun st => b * st Y + st X = a }}
END
{{ fun st => b * st Y + st X = a ∧ ~(bassn (BLe (ANum b) (AId X)) st) }} =>
{{ fun st => b * st Y + st X = a ∧ (st X < b) }}
)%dcom.
Theorem div_mod_dec_correct : ∀a b,
dec_correct (div_mod_dec a b).
Proof.
intros a b. verify.
Case "1". apply ble_nat_true in H0. rewrite mult_plus_distr_l. omega.
Case "2". apply ble_nat_false in H0. omega.
(* more automation would help here *)
Qed.