StlcThe Simply Typed Lambda-Calculus
(* $Date: 2012-07-25 16:43:16 -0400 (Wed, 25 Jul 2012) $ *)
Require Export Types.
The Simply Typed Lambda-Calculus
Overview
- variables
- function abstractions
- application
t ::= x variable | \x:T.t1 abstraction | t1 t2 application | true constant true | false constant false | if t1 then t2 else t3 conditional
- \x:Bool. x
- (\x:Bool. x) true
- \x:Bool. if x then false else true
- \x:Bool. true
- \x:Bool. \y:Bool. x
- (\x:Bool. \y:Bool. x) false true
- \f:Bool→Bool. f (f true)
- (\f:Bool→Bool. f (f true)) (\x:Bool. false)
T ::= Bool | T1 -> T2For example:
- \x:Bool. false has type Bool→Bool
- \x:Bool. x has type Bool→Bool
- (\x:Bool. x) true has type Bool
- \x:Bool. \y:Bool. x has type Bool→Bool→Bool (i.e. Bool → (Bool→Bool))
- (\x:Bool. \y:Bool. x) false has type Bool→Bool
- (\x:Bool. \y:Bool. x) false true has type Bool
- \f:Bool→Bool. f (f true) has type (Bool→Bool) → Bool
- (\f:Bool→Bool. f (f true)) (\x:Bool. false) has type Bool
Module STLC.
Inductive ty : Type :=
| TBool : ty
| TArrow : ty → ty → ty.
Inductive tm : Type :=
| tvar : id → tm
| tapp : tm → tm → tm
| tabs : id → ty → tm → tm
| ttrue : tm
| tfalse : tm
| tif : tm → tm → tm → tm.
Tactic Notation "t_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "tvar" | Case_aux c "tapp"
| Case_aux c "tabs" | Case_aux c "ttrue"
| Case_aux c "tfalse" | Case_aux c "tif" ].
first;
[ Case_aux c "tvar" | Case_aux c "tapp"
| Case_aux c "tabs" | Case_aux c "ttrue"
| Case_aux c "tfalse" | Case_aux c "tif" ].
Note that an abstraction \x:T.t (formally, tabs x T t) is
always annotated with the type T of its parameter, in contrast
to Coq (and other functional languages like ML, Haskell, etc.),
which use type inference to fill in missing annotations. We're
not considering type inference here, to keep things simple.
Some examples...
Definition x := (Id 0).
Definition y := (Id 1).
Definition z := (Id 2).
Hint Unfold x.
Hint Unfold y.
Hint Unfold z.
Hint Unfold y.
Hint Unfold z.
idB = \x:Bool. x
Notation idB :=
(tabs x TBool (tvar x)).
idBB = \x:Bool→Bool. x
Notation idBB :=
(tabs x (TArrow TBool TBool) (tvar x)).
idBBBB = \x:(Bool→Bool)->(Bool→Bool). x
Notation idBBBB :=
(tabs x (TArrow (TArrow TBool TBool)
(TArrow TBool TBool))
(tvar x)).
k = \x:Bool. \y:Bool. x
Notation k := (tabs x TBool (tabs y TBool (tvar x))).
(We write these as Notations rather than Definitions to make
things easier for auto.)
Operational Semantics
Values
- We can say that \x:T.t1 is a value only when t1 is a
value — i.e., only if the function's body has been
reduced (as much as it can be without knowing what argument it
is going to be applied to).
- Or we can say that \x:T.t1 is always a value, no matter whether t1 is one or not — in other words, we can say that reduction stops at abstractions.
Eval simpl in (fun x:bool => 3 + 4)
yields fun x:bool => 7. But most real-world functional
programming languages make the second choice — reduction of a
function's body only begins when the function is actually applied
to an argument. We also make the second choice here.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_abs : ∀x T t,
value (tabs x T t)
| t_true :
value ttrue
| t_false :
value tfalse.
Hint Constructors value.
Free Variables and Substitution
(\x:Bool. if x then true else x) false
to false by substituting false for the parameter x in the
body of the function. In general, we need to be able to
substitute some given term s for occurrences of some variable
x in another term t. In informal discussions, this is usually
written [x:=s]t and pronounced "substitute x with s in t."
- [x:=true] (if x then x else false) yields if true then true else false
- [x:=true] x yields true
- [x:=true] (if x then x else y) yields if true then true else y
- [x:=true] y yields y
- [x:=true] false yields false (vacuous substitution)
- [x:=true] (\y:Bool. if y then x else false) yields \y:Bool. if y then true else false
- [x:=true] (\y:Bool. x) yields \y:Bool. true
- [x:=true] (\y:Bool. y) yields \y:Bool. y
- [x:=true] (\x:Bool. x) yields \x:Bool. x
[x:=s]x = s
[x:=s]y = y if x <> y
[x:=s](\x:T11.t12) = \x:T11. t12
[x:=s](\y:T11.t12) = \y:T11. [x:=s]t12 if x <> y
[x:=s](t1 t2) = ([x:=s]t1) ([x:=s]t2)
[x:=s]true = true
[x:=s]false = false
[x:=s](if t1 then t2 else t3) =
if [x:=s]t1 then [x:=s]t2 else [x:=s]t3
... and formally:
[x:=s]y = y if x <> y
[x:=s](\x:T11.t12) = \x:T11. t12
[x:=s](\y:T11.t12) = \y:T11. [x:=s]t12 if x <> y
[x:=s](t1 t2) = ([x:=s]t1) ([x:=s]t2)
[x:=s]true = true
[x:=s]false = false
[x:=s](if t1 then t2 else t3) =
if [x:=s]t1 then [x:=s]t2 else [x:=s]t3
Fixpoint subst (x:id) (s:tm) (t:tm) : tm :=
match t with
| tvar x' =>
if beq_id x x' then s else t
| tabs x' T t1 =>
tabs x' T (if beq_id x x' then t1 else (subst x s t1))
| tapp t1 t2 =>
tapp (subst x s t1) (subst x s t2)
| ttrue =>
ttrue
| tfalse =>
tfalse
| tif t1 t2 t3 =>
tif (subst x s t1) (subst x s t2) (subst x s t3)
end.
Notation "'[' x ':=' s ']' t" := (subst x s t) (at level 20).
Technical note: Substitution becomes trickier to define if we
consider the case where s, the term being substituted for a
variable in some other term, may itself contain free variables.
Since we are only interested here in defining the step relation
on closed terms (i.e., terms like \x:Bool. x y that mention
variables are not bound by some enclosing lambda), we can avoid
this extra complexity here.
Reduction
(\x:T.t12) v2 ⇒ [x:=v2]t12
is traditionally called "beta-reduction".
value v2 | (ST_AppAbs) |
(\x:T.t12) v2 ⇒ [x:=v2]t12 |
t1 ⇒ t1' | (ST_App1) |
t1 t2 ⇒ t1' t2 |
value v1 | |
t2 ⇒ t2' | (ST_App2) |
v1 t2 ⇒ v1 t2' |
(ST_IfTrue) | |
(if true then t1 else t2) ⇒ t1 |
(ST_IfFalse) | |
(if false then t1 else t2) ⇒ t2 |
t1 ⇒ t1' | (ST_If) |
(if t1 then t2 else t3) ⇒ (if t1' then t2 else t3) |
Reserved Notation "t1 '⇒' t2" (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_AppAbs : ∀x T t12 v2,
value v2 →
(tapp (tabs x T t12) v2) ⇒ [x:=v2]t12
| ST_App1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
tapp t1 t2 ⇒ tapp t1' t2
| ST_App2 : ∀v1 t2 t2',
value v1 →
t2 ⇒ t2' →
tapp v1 t2 ⇒ tapp v1 t2'
| ST_IfTrue : ∀t1 t2,
(tif ttrue t1 t2) ⇒ t1
| ST_IfFalse : ∀t1 t2,
(tif tfalse t1 t2) ⇒ t2
| ST_If : ∀t1 t1' t2 t3,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
(tif t1 t2 t3) ⇒ (tif t1' t2 t3)
where "t1 '⇒' t2" := (step t1 t2).
Tactic Notation "step_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "ST_AppAbs" | Case_aux c "ST_App1"
| Case_aux c "ST_App2" | Case_aux c "ST_IfTrue"
| Case_aux c "ST_IfFalse" | Case_aux c "ST_If" ].
Hint Constructors step.
Notation multistep := (multi step).
Notation "t1 '⇒*' t2" := (multistep t1 t2) (at level 40).
Lemma step_example1 :
(tapp idBB idB) ⇒* idB.
Proof.
eapply multi_step.
apply ST_AppAbs.
apply v_abs.
simpl.
apply multi_refl. Qed.
A more automatic proof
Lemma step_example1' :
(tapp idBB idB) ⇒* idB.
Proof. normalize. Qed.
Lemma step_example2 :
(tapp idBB (tapp idBB idB)) ⇒* idB.
Proof.
eapply multi_step.
apply ST_App2. auto.
apply ST_AppAbs. auto.
eapply multi_step.
apply ST_AppAbs. simpl. auto.
simpl. apply multi_refl. Qed.
Again, we can use the normalize tactic from above to simplify
the proof.
Lemma step_example2' :
(tapp idBB (tapp idBB idB)) ⇒* idB.
Proof.
normalize.
Qed.
Lemma step_example3 :
(tapp (tapp idBBBB idBB) idB)
⇒* idB.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Contexts
Module PartialMap.
Definition partial_map (A:Type) := id → option A.
Definition empty {A:Type} : partial_map A := (fun _ => None).
Informally, we'll write Γ, x:T for "extend the partial
function Γ to also map x to T." Formally, we use the
function extend to add a binding to a partial map.
Definition extend {A:Type} (Γ : partial_map A) (x:id) (T : A) :=
fun x' => if beq_id x x' then Some T else Γ x'.
Lemma extend_eq : ∀A (ctxt: partial_map A) x T,
(extend ctxt x T) x = Some T.
Proof.
intros. unfold extend. rewrite ← beq_id_refl. auto.
Qed.
intros. unfold extend. rewrite ← beq_id_refl. auto.
Qed.
Lemma extend_neq : ∀A (ctxt: partial_map A) x1 T x2,
beq_id x2 x1 = false →
(extend ctxt x2 T) x1 = ctxt x1.
Proof.
intros. unfold extend. rewrite H. auto.
Qed.
intros. unfold extend. rewrite H. auto.
Qed.
End PartialMap.
Definition context := partial_map ty.
Typing Relation
Γ x = T | (T_Var) |
Γ ⊢ x : T |
Γ , x:T11 ⊢ t12 : T12 | (T_Abs) |
Γ ⊢ \x:T11.t12 : T11->T12 |
Γ ⊢ t1 : T11->T12 | |
Γ ⊢ t2 : T11 | (T_App) |
Γ ⊢ t1 t2 : T12 |
(T_True) | |
Γ ⊢ true : Bool |
(T_False) | |
Γ ⊢ false : Bool |
Γ ⊢ t1 : Bool Γ ⊢ t2 : T Γ ⊢ t3 : T | (T_If) |
Γ ⊢ if t1 then t2 else t3 : T |
Inductive has_type : context → tm → ty → Prop :=
| T_Var : ∀Γ x T,
Γ x = Some T →
has_type Γ (tvar x) T
| T_Abs : ∀Γ x T11 T12 t12,
has_type (extend Γ x T11) t12 T12 →
has_type Γ (tabs x T11 t12) (TArrow T11 T12)
| T_App : ∀T11 T12 Γ t1 t2,
has_type Γ t1 (TArrow T11 T12) →
has_type Γ t2 T11 →
has_type Γ (tapp t1 t2) T12
| T_True : ∀Γ,
has_type Γ ttrue TBool
| T_False : ∀Γ,
has_type Γ tfalse TBool
| T_If : ∀t1 t2 t3 T Γ,
has_type Γ t1 TBool →
has_type Γ t2 T →
has_type Γ t3 T →
has_type Γ (tif t1 t2 t3) T.
Tactic Notation "has_type_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "T_Var" | Case_aux c "T_Abs"
| Case_aux c "T_App" | Case_aux c "T_True"
| Case_aux c "T_False" | Case_aux c "T_If" ].
Hint Constructors has_type.
first;
[ Case_aux c "T_Var" | Case_aux c "T_Abs"
| Case_aux c "T_App" | Case_aux c "T_True"
| Case_aux c "T_False" | Case_aux c "T_If" ].
Hint Constructors has_type.
Example typing_example_1 :
has_type empty (tabs x TBool (tvar x)) (TArrow TBool TBool).
Proof.
apply T_Abs. apply T_Var. reflexivity. Qed.
Note that since we added the has_type constructors to the hints
database, auto can actually solve this one immediately.
Example typing_example_1' :
has_type empty (tabs x TBool (tvar x)) (TArrow TBool TBool).
Proof. auto. Qed.
Hint Unfold beq_id beq_nat extend.
Another example:
empty ⊢ \x:A. \y:A→A. y (y x))
: A → (A→A) → A.
: A → (A→A) → A.
Example typing_example_2 :
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tapp (tvar y) (tapp (tvar y) (tvar x)))))
(TArrow TBool (TArrow (TArrow TBool TBool) TBool)).
Proof with auto using extend_eq.
apply T_Abs.
apply T_Abs.
eapply T_App. apply T_Var...
eapply T_App. apply T_Var...
apply T_Var...
Qed.
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tapp (tvar y) (tapp (tvar y) (tvar x)))))
(TArrow TBool (TArrow (TArrow TBool TBool) TBool)).
Proof with auto using extend_eq.
apply T_Abs.
apply T_Abs.
eapply T_App. apply T_Var...
eapply T_App. apply T_Var...
apply T_Var...
Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (typing_example_2_full)
Prove the same result without using auto, eauto, or eapply.Example typing_example_2_full :
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tapp (tvar y) (tapp (tvar y) (tvar x)))))
(TArrow TBool (TArrow (TArrow TBool TBool) TBool)).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 2 stars (typing_example_3)
Formally prove the following typing derivation holds:
empty ⊢ (\x:Bool→B. \y:Bool→Bool. \z:Bool.
y (x z))
: T.
y (x z))
: T.
Example typing_example_3 :
∃T,
has_type empty
(tabs x (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tabs y (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tabs z TBool
(tapp (tvar y) (tapp (tvar x) (tvar z))))))
T.
Proof with auto.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
∃T,
has_type empty
(tabs x (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tabs y (TArrow TBool TBool)
(tabs z TBool
(tapp (tvar y) (tapp (tvar x) (tvar z))))))
T.
Proof with auto.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
We can also show that terms are not typable. For example, let's
formally check that there is no typing derivation assigning a type
to the term \x:Bool. \y:Bool, x y — i.e.,
~ ∃ T,
empty ⊢ (\x:Bool. \y:Bool, x y) : T.
empty ⊢ (\x:Bool. \y:Bool, x y) : T.
Example typing_nonexample_1 :
~ ∃T,
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y TBool
(tapp (tvar x) (tvar y))))
T.
Proof.
intros Hc. inversion Hc.
(* The clear tactic is useful here for tidying away bits of
the context that we're not going to need again. *)
inversion H. subst. clear H.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
inversion H4. subst. clear H4.
inversion H2. subst. clear H2.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
(* rewrite extend_neq in H1. rewrite extend_eq in H1. *)
inversion H1. Qed.
~ ∃T,
has_type empty
(tabs x TBool
(tabs y TBool
(tapp (tvar x) (tvar y))))
T.
Proof.
intros Hc. inversion Hc.
(* The clear tactic is useful here for tidying away bits of
the context that we're not going to need again. *)
inversion H. subst. clear H.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
inversion H4. subst. clear H4.
inversion H2. subst. clear H2.
inversion H5. subst. clear H5.
(* rewrite extend_neq in H1. rewrite extend_eq in H1. *)
inversion H1. Qed.
Example typing_nonexample_3 :
~ (∃S, ∃T,
has_type empty
(tabs x S
(tapp (tvar x) (tvar x)))
T).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Which of the following propositions are provable?
☐
Which of the following propositions are provable? For the
ones that are, give witnesses for the existentially bound
variables.
☐
Exercise: 1 star, optional (typing_statements)
- y:Bool ⊢ \x:Bool.x : Bool→Bool
- ∃ T, empty ⊢ (\y:Bool→Bool. \x:Bool. y x) : T
- ∃ T, empty ⊢ (\y:Bool→Bool. \x:Bool. x y) : T
- ∃ S, x:S ⊢ (\y:Bool→Bool. y) x : S
- ∃ S, ∃ T, x:S ⊢ (x x x) : T
Exercise: 1 star (more_typing_statements)
- ∃ T, empty ⊢ (\y:B→B→B. \x:B, y x) : T
- ∃ T, empty ⊢ (\x:A→B, \y:B→C, \z:A, y (x z)):T
- ∃ S, ∃ U, ∃ T, x:S, y:U ⊢ \z:A. x (y z) : T
- ∃ S, ∃ T, x:S ⊢ \y:A. x (x y) : T
- ∃ S, ∃ U, ∃ T, x:S ⊢ x (\z:U. z x) : T
Progress
Theorem progress : ∀t T,
has_type empty t T →
value t ∨ ∃t', t ⇒ t'.
Proof: by induction on the derivation of ⊢ t : T.
- The last rule of the derivation cannot be T_Var, since a
variable is never well typed in an empty context.
- The T_True, T_False, and T_Abs cases are trivial, since in
each of these cases we know immediately that t is a value.
- If the last rule of the derivation was T_App, then t = t1
t2, and we know that t1 and t2 are also well typed in the
empty context; in particular, there exists a type T2 such that
⊢ t1 : T2 → T and ⊢ t2 : T2. By the induction
hypothesis, either t1 is a value or it can take an evaluation
step.
- If t1 is a value, we now consider t2, which by the other
induction hypothesis must also either be a value or take an
evaluation step.
- Suppose t2 is a value. Since t1 is a value with an
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence t1
t2 can take a step by ST_AppAbs.
- Otherwise, t2 can take a step, and hence so can t1
t2 by ST_App2.
- Suppose t2 is a value. Since t1 is a value with an
arrow type, it must be a lambda abstraction; hence t1
t2 can take a step by ST_AppAbs.
- If t1 can take a step, then so can t1 t2 by ST_App1.
- If t1 is a value, we now consider t2, which by the other
induction hypothesis must also either be a value or take an
evaluation step.
- If the last rule of the derivation was T_If, then t = if t1
then t2 else t3, where t1 has type Bool. By the IH, t1
is either a value or takes a step.
- If t1 is a value, then since it has type Bool it must be
either true or false. If it is true, then t steps
to t2; otherwise it steps to t3.
- Otherwise, t1 takes a step, and therefore so does t (by ST_If).
- If t1 is a value, then since it has type Bool it must be
either true or false. If it is true, then t steps
to t2; otherwise it steps to t3.
Proof with eauto.
intros t T Ht.
remember (@empty ty) as Γ.
has_type_cases (induction Ht) Case; subst Γ...
Case "T_Var".
(* contradictory: variables cannot be typed in an
empty context *)
inversion H.
Case "T_App".
(* t = t1 t2. Proceed by cases on whether t1 is a
value or steps... *)
right. destruct IHHt1...
SCase "t1 is a value".
destruct IHHt2...
SSCase "t2 is also a value".
(* Since t1 is a value and has an arrow type, it
must be an abs. Sometimes this is proved separately
and called a "canonical forms" lemma. *)
inversion H; subst. ∃([x0:=t2]t)...
solve by inversion. solve by inversion.
SSCase "t2 steps".
inversion H0 as [t2' Hstp]. ∃(tapp t1 t2')...
SCase "t1 steps".
inversion H as [t1' Hstp]. ∃(tapp t1' t2)...
Case "T_If".
right. destruct IHHt1...
SCase "t1 is a value".
(* Since t1 is a value of boolean type, it must
be true or false *)
inversion H; subst. solve by inversion.
SSCase "t1 = true". eauto.
SSCase "t1 = false". eauto.
SCase "t1 also steps".
inversion H as [t1' Hstp]. ∃(tif t1' t2 t3)...
Qed.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (progress_from_term_ind)
Show that progress can also be proved by induction on terms instead of induction on typing derivations.Theorem progress' : ∀t T,
has_type empty t T →
value t ∨ ∃t', t ⇒ t'.
Proof.
intros t.
t_cases (induction t) Case; intros T Ht; auto.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Free Occurrences
- y appears free, but x does not, in \x:T→U. x y
- both x and y appear free in (\x:T→U. x y) x
- no variables appear free in \x:T→U. \y:T. x y
Inductive appears_free_in : id → tm → Prop :=
| afi_var : ∀x,
appears_free_in x (tvar x)
| afi_app1 : ∀x t1 t2,
appears_free_in x t1 → appears_free_in x (tapp t1 t2)
| afi_app2 : ∀x t1 t2,
appears_free_in x t2 → appears_free_in x (tapp t1 t2)
| afi_abs : ∀x y T11 t12,
y <> x →
appears_free_in x t12 →
appears_free_in x (tabs y T11 t12)
| afi_if1 : ∀x t1 t2 t3,
appears_free_in x t1 →
appears_free_in x (tif t1 t2 t3)
| afi_if2 : ∀x t1 t2 t3,
appears_free_in x t2 →
appears_free_in x (tif t1 t2 t3)
| afi_if3 : ∀x t1 t2 t3,
appears_free_in x t3 →
appears_free_in x (tif t1 t2 t3).
Tactic Notation "afi_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "afi_var"
| Case_aux c "afi_app1" | Case_aux c "afi_app2"
| Case_aux c "afi_abs"
| Case_aux c "afi_if1" | Case_aux c "afi_if2"
| Case_aux c "afi_if3" ].
Hint Constructors appears_free_in.
first;
[ Case_aux c "afi_var"
| Case_aux c "afi_app1" | Case_aux c "afi_app2"
| Case_aux c "afi_abs"
| Case_aux c "afi_if1" | Case_aux c "afi_if2"
| Case_aux c "afi_if3" ].
Hint Constructors appears_free_in.
A term in which no variables appear free is said to be closed.
Definition closed (t:tm) :=
∀x, ~ appears_free_in x t.
Substitution
Lemma free_in_context : ∀x t T Γ,
appears_free_in x t →
has_type Γ t T →
∃T', Γ x = Some T'.
Proof: We show, by induction on the proof that x appears free
in t, that, for all contexts Γ, if t is well typed
under Γ, then Γ assigns some type to x.
- If the last rule used was afi_var, then t = x, and from
the assumption that t is well typed under Γ we have
immediately that Γ assigns a type to x.
- If the last rule used was afi_app1, then t = t1 t2 and x
appears free in t1. Since t is well typed under Γ,
we can see from the typing rules that t1 must also be, and
the IH then tells us that Γ assigns x a type.
- Almost all the other cases are similar: x appears free in a
subterm of t, and since t is well typed under Γ, we
know the subterm of t in which x appears is well typed
under Γ as well, and the IH gives us exactly the
conclusion we want.
- The only remaining case is afi_abs. In this case t = \y:T11.t12, and x appears free in t12; we also know that x is different from y. The difference from the previous cases is that whereas t is well typed under Γ, its body t12 is well typed under (Γ, y:T11), so the IH allows us to conclude that x is assigned some type by the extended context (Γ, y:T11). To conclude that Γ assigns a type to x, we appeal to lemma extend_neq, noting that x and y are different variables.
Proof.
intros x t T Γ H H0. generalize dependent Γ.
generalize dependent T.
afi_cases (induction H) Case;
intros; try solve [inversion H0; eauto].
Case "afi_abs".
inversion H1; subst.
apply IHappears_free_in in H7.
apply not_eq_beq_id_false in H.
rewrite extend_neq in H7; assumption.
Qed.
Next, we'll need the fact that any term t which is well typed in
the empty context is closed — that is, it has no free variables.
Exercise: 2 stars (typable_empty__closed)
Corollary typable_empty__closed : ∀t T,
has_type empty t T →
closed t.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
has_type empty t T →
closed t.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Sometimes, when we have a proof Γ ⊢ t : T, we will need to
replace Γ by a different context Γ'. When is it safe
to do this? Intuitively, it must at least be the case that
Γ' assigns the same types as Γ to all the variables
that appear free in t. In fact, this is the only condition that
is needed.
Lemma context_invariance : ∀Γ Γ' t T,
has_type Γ t T →
(∀x, appears_free_in x t → Γ x = Γ' x) →
has_type Γ' t T.
Proof: By induction on the derivation of Γ ⊢ t : T.
- If the last rule in the derivation was T_Var, then t = x
and Γ x = T. By assumption, Γ' x = T as well, and
hence Γ' ⊢ t : T by T_Var.
- If the last rule was T_Abs, then t = \y:T11. t12, with T
= T11 → T12 and Γ, y:T11 ⊢ t12 : T12. The induction
hypothesis is that for any context Γ'', if Γ,
y:T11 and Γ'' assign the same types to all the free
variables in t12, then t12 has type T12 under Γ''.
Let Γ' be a context which agrees with Γ on the
free variables in t; we must show Γ' ⊢ \y:T11. t12 :
T11 → T12.
- If the last rule was T_App, then t = t1 t2, with Γ ⊢ t1 : T2 → T and Γ ⊢ t2 : T2. One induction hypothesis states that for all contexts Γ', if Γ' agrees with Γ on the free variables in t1, then t1 has type T2 → T under Γ'; there is a similar IH for t2. We must show that t1 t2 also has type T under Γ', given the assumption that Γ' agrees with Γ on all the free variables in t1 t2. By T_App, it suffices to show that t1 and t2 each have the same type under Γ' as under Γ. However, we note that all free variables in t1 are also free in t1 t2, and similarly for free variables in t2; hence the desired result follows by the two IHs.
Proof with eauto.
intros.
generalize dependent Γ'.
has_type_cases (induction H) Case; intros; auto.
Case "T_Var".
apply T_Var. rewrite ← H0...
Case "T_Abs".
apply T_Abs.
apply IHhas_type. intros x1 Hafi.
(* the only tricky step... the Γ' we use to
instantiate is extend Γ x T11 *)
unfold extend. remember (beq_id x0 x1) as e. destruct e...
Case "T_App".
apply T_App with T11...
Qed.
Now we come to the conceptual heart of the proof that reduction
preserves types — namely, the observation that substitution
preserves types.
Formally, the so-called Substitution Lemma says this: suppose we
have a term t with a free variable x, and suppose we've been
able to assign a type T to t under the assumption that x has
some type U. Also, suppose that we have some other term v and
that we've shown that v has type U. Then, since v satisfies
the assumption we made about x when typing t, we should be
able to substitute v for each of the occurrences of x in t
and obtain a new term that still has type T.
Lemma: If Γ,x:U ⊢ t : T and ⊢ v : U, then Γ ⊢
[x:=v]t : T.
Lemma substitution_preserves_typing : ∀Γ x U t t' T,
has_type (extend Γ x U) t T →
has_type empty t' U →
has_type Γ ([x:=t']t) T.
One technical subtlety in the statement of the lemma is that we
assign t' the type U in the empty context — in other words,
we assume t' is closed. This assumption considerably simplifies
the T_Abs case of the proof (compared to assuming Γ ⊢ t' :
U, which would be the other reasonable assumption at this point)
because the context invariance lemma then tells us that t' has
type U in any context at all — we don't have to worry about
free variables in t' clashing with the variable being introduced
into the context by T_Abs.
Proof: We prove, by induction on t, that, for all T and
Γ, if Γ,x:U ⊢ t : T and ⊢ t' : U, then Γ ⊢
[x:=t']t : T.
Another technical note: This proof is a rare case where an
induction on terms, rather than typing derivations, yields a
simpler argument. The reason for this is that the assumption
has_type (extend Γ x U) t T is not completely generic, in
the sense that one of the "slots" in the typing relation — namely
the context — is not just a variable, and this means that Coq's
native induction tactic does not give us the induction hypothesis
that we want. It is possible to work around this, but the needed
generalization is a little tricky. The term t, on the other
hand, is completely generic.
- If t is a variable, there are two cases to consider, depending
on whether t is x or some other variable.
- If t = x, then from the fact that Γ, x:U ⊢ x : T we
conclude that U = T. We must show that [x:=t']x = t' has
type T under Γ, given the assumption that t' has
type U = T under the empty context. This follows from
context invariance: if a closed term has type T in the
empty context, it has that type in any context.
- If t is some variable y that is not equal to x, then
we need only note that y has the same type under Γ,
x:U as under Γ.
- If t = x, then from the fact that Γ, x:U ⊢ x : T we
conclude that U = T. We must show that [x:=t']x = t' has
type T under Γ, given the assumption that t' has
type U = T under the empty context. This follows from
context invariance: if a closed term has type T in the
empty context, it has that type in any context.
- If t is an abstraction \y:T11. t12, then the IH tells us,
for all Γ' and T', that if Γ',x:U ⊢ t12 : T'
and ⊢ t' : U, then Γ' ⊢ [x:=t']t12 : T'.
- If t is an application t1 t2, the result follows
straightforwardly from the definition of substitution and the
induction hypotheses.
- The remaining cases are similar to the application case.
Proof with eauto.
intros Γ x U t t' T Ht Ht'.
generalize dependent Γ. generalize dependent T.
t_cases (induction t) Case; intros T Γ H;
(* in each case, we'll want to get at the derivation of H *)
inversion H; subst; simpl...
Case "tvar".
rename i into y. remember (beq_id x y) as e. destruct e.
SCase "x=y".
apply beq_id_eq in Heqe. subst.
rewrite extend_eq in H2.
inversion H2; subst. clear H2.
eapply context_invariance... intros x Hcontra.
destruct (free_in_context _ _ T empty Hcontra) as [T' HT']...
inversion HT'.
SCase "x<>y".
apply T_Var. rewrite extend_neq in H2...
Case "tabs".
rename i into y. apply T_Abs.
remember (beq_id x y) as e. destruct e.
SCase "x=y".
eapply context_invariance...
apply beq_id_eq in Heqe. subst.
intros x Hafi. unfold extend.
destruct (beq_id y x)...
SCase "x<>y".
apply IHt. eapply context_invariance...
intros z Hafi. unfold extend.
remember (beq_id y z) as e0. destruct e0...
apply beq_id_eq in Heqe0. subst.
rewrite ← Heqe...
Qed.
The substitution lemma can be viewed as a kind of "commutation"
property. Intuitively, it says that substitution and typing can
be done in either order: we can either assign types to the terms
t and v separately (under suitable contexts) and then combine
them using substitution, or we can substitute first and then
assign a type to [x:=v] t — the result is the same either
way.
Preservation
Theorem preservation : ∀t t' T,
has_type empty t T →
t ⇒ t' →
has_type empty t' T.
Proof: by induction on the derivation of ⊢ t : T.
- We can immediately rule out T_Var, T_Abs, T_True, and
T_False as the final rules in the derivation, since in each of
these cases t cannot take a step.
- If the last rule in the derivation was T_App, then t = t1
t2. There are three cases to consider, one for each rule that
could have been used to show that t1 t2 takes a step to t'.
- If t1 t2 takes a step by ST_App1, with t1 stepping to
t1', then by the IH t1' has the same type as t1, and
hence t1' t2 has the same type as t1 t2.
- The ST_App2 case is similar.
- If t1 t2 takes a step by ST_AppAbs, then t1 =
\x:T11.t12 and t1 t2 steps to [x:=t2]t12; the
desired result now follows from the fact that substitution
preserves types.
- If t1 t2 takes a step by ST_App1, with t1 stepping to
t1', then by the IH t1' has the same type as t1, and
hence t1' t2 has the same type as t1 t2.
- If the last rule in the derivation was T_If, then t = if t1
then t2 else t3, and there are again three cases depending on
how t steps.
- If t steps to t2 or t3, the result is immediate, since
t2 and t3 have the same type as t.
- Otherwise, t steps by ST_If, and the desired conclusion follows directly from the induction hypothesis.
- If t steps to t2 or t3, the result is immediate, since
t2 and t3 have the same type as t.
Proof with eauto.
remember (@empty ty) as Γ.
intros t t' T HT. generalize dependent t'.
has_type_cases (induction HT) Case;
intros t' HE; subst Γ; subst;
try solve [inversion HE; subst; auto].
Case "T_App".
inversion HE; subst...
(* Most of the cases are immediate by induction,
and eauto takes care of them *)
SCase "ST_AppAbs".
apply substitution_preserves_typing with T11...
inversion HT1...
Qed.
Exercise: 2 stars, recommended (subject_expansion_stlc)
An exercise in Types.v asked about the subject expansion property for the simple language of arithmetic and boolean expressions. Does this property hold for STLC? That is, is it always the case that, if t ⇒ t' and has_type t' T, then has_type t T? If so, prove it. If not, give a counter-example.☐
Type Soundness
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (type_soundness)
Definition stuck (t:tm) : Prop :=
(normal_form step) t ∧ ~ value t.
Corollary soundness : ∀t t' T,
has_type empty t T →
t ⇒* t' →
~(stuck t').
Proof.
intros t t' T Hhas_type Hmulti. unfold stuck.
intros [Hnf Hnot_val]. unfold normal_form in Hnf.
induction Hmulti.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Uniqueness of Types
Exercise: 3 stars (types_unique)
Another pleasant property of the STLC is that types are unique: a given term (in a given context) has at most one type. Formalize this statement and prove it.(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Additional Exercises
Exercise: 1 star (progress_preservation_statement)
Without peeking, write down the progress and preservation theorems for the simply typed lambda-calculus. ☐Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation1)
Suppose we add a new term zap with the following reduction rule:(ST_Zap) | |
t ⇒ zap |
(T_Zap) | |
Γ ⊢ zap : T |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation2)
Suppose instead that we add a new term foo with the following reduction rules:(ST_Foo1) | |
(\x:A. x) ⇒ foo |
(ST_Foo2) | |
foo ⇒ true |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation3)
Suppose instead that we remove the rule ST_App1 from the step relation. Which of the following properties of the STLC remain true in the presence of this rule? For each one, write either "remains true" or else "becomes false." If a property becomes false, give a counterexample.- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation4)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the reduction relation:(ST_FunnyIfTrue) | |
(if true then t1 else t2) ⇒ true |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation5)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing relation:Γ ⊢ t1 : Bool->Bool->Bool | |
Γ ⊢ t2 : Bool | (T_FunnyApp) |
Γ ⊢ t1 t2 : Bool |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation6)
Suppose instead that we add the following new rule to the typing relation:Γ ⊢ t1 : Bool | |
Γ ⊢ t2 : Bool | (T_FunnyApp') |
Γ ⊢ t1 t2 : Bool |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
Exercise: 2 stars (stlc_variation7)
Suppose we add the following new rule to the typing relation of the STLC:(T_FunnyAbs) | |
⊢ \x:Bool.t : Bool |
- Determinism of step
- Progress
- Preservation
End STLC.
Optional Exercise: STLC with Arithmetic
Module STLCArith.
Syntax and Operational Semantics
Inductive ty : Type :=
| TArrow : ty → ty → ty
| TNat : ty.
To terms, we add natural number constants, along with
successor, predecessor, multiplication, and zero-testing...
Inductive tm : Type :=
| tvar : id → tm
| tapp : tm → tm → tm
| tabs : id → ty → tm → tm
| tnat : nat → tm
| tsucc : tm → tm
| tpred : tm → tm
| tmult : tm → tm → tm
| tif0 : tm → tm → tm → tm.
Tactic Notation "t_cases" tactic(first) ident(c) :=
first;
[ Case_aux c "tvar" | Case_aux c "tapp"
| Case_aux c "tabs" | Case_aux c "tnat"
| Case_aux c "tsucc" | Case_aux c "tpred"
| Case_aux c "tmult" | Case_aux c "tif0" ].
first;
[ Case_aux c "tvar" | Case_aux c "tapp"
| Case_aux c "tabs" | Case_aux c "tnat"
| Case_aux c "tsucc" | Case_aux c "tpred"
| Case_aux c "tmult" | Case_aux c "tif0" ].
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (stlc_arith)
Finish formalizing the definition and properties of the STLC extended with arithmetic. Specifically:- Copy the whole development of STLC that we went through above (from
the definition of values through the Progress theorem), and
paste it into the file at this point.
- Extend the definitions of the subst operation and the step
relation to include appropriate clauses for the arithmetic operators.
- Extend the proofs of all the properties of the original STLC to deal with the new syntactic forms. Make sure Coq accepts the whole file.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
End STLCArith.