ImpSimple Imperative Programs
Z ::= X;;
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
Set Warnings "-notation-overridden,-parsing".
Require Import Coq.Bool.Bool.
Require Import Coq.Arith.Arith.
Require Import Coq.Arith.EqNat.
Require Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Require Import Coq.Lists.List.
Require Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Import ListNotations.
Require Import Maps.
Require Import Coq.Bool.Bool.
Require Import Coq.Arith.Arith.
Require Import Coq.Arith.EqNat.
Require Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Require Import Coq.Lists.List.
Require Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Import ListNotations.
Require Import Maps.
Arithmetic and Boolean Expressions
These two definitions specify the abstract syntax of
arithmetic and boolean expressions.
Inductive aexp : Type :=
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
Inductive bexp : Type :=
| BTrue : bexp
| BFalse : bexp
| BEq : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BLe : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BNot : bexp → bexp
| BAnd : bexp → bexp → bexp.
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
Inductive bexp : Type :=
| BTrue : bexp
| BFalse : bexp
| BEq : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BLe : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BNot : bexp → bexp
| BAnd : bexp → bexp → bexp.
In this chapter, we'll mostly elide the translation from the
concrete syntax that a programmer would actually write to these
abstract syntax trees — the process that, for example, would
translate the string "1+2*3" to the AST
For comparison, here's a conventional BNF (Backus-Naur Form)
grammar defining the same abstract syntax:
Compared to the Coq version above...
It's good to be comfortable with both sorts of notations: informal
ones for communicating between humans and formal ones for carrying
out implementations and proofs.
APlus (ANum 1) (AMult (ANum 2) (ANum 3)).
The optional chapter ImpParser develops a simple
implementation of a lexical analyzer and parser that can perform
this translation. You do not need to understand that chapter to
understand this one, but if you haven't taken a course where these
techniques are covered (e.g., a compilers course) you may want to
skim it.
a ::= nat
| a + a
| a - a
| a * a
b ::= true
| false
| a = a
| a ≤ a
| not b
| b and b
| a + a
| a - a
| a * a
b ::= true
| false
| a = a
| a ≤ a
| not b
| b and b
- The BNF is more informal — for example, it gives some
suggestions about the surface syntax of expressions (like the
fact that the addition operation is written + and is an
infix symbol) while leaving other aspects of lexical analysis
and parsing (like the relative precedence of +, -, and
*, the use of parens to explicitly group subexpressions,
etc.) unspecified. Some additional information (and human
intelligence) would be required to turn this description into
a formal definition, for example when implementing a
compiler.
- On the other hand, the BNF version is lighter and easier to
read. Its informality makes it flexible, a big advantage in
situations like discussions at the blackboard, where
conveying general ideas is more important than getting every
detail nailed down precisely.
Fixpoint aeval (a : aexp) : nat :=
match a with
| ANum n ⇒ n
| APlus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) + (aeval a2)
| AMinus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) - (aeval a2)
| AMult a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) * (aeval a2)
end.
Example test_aeval1:
aeval (APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 2)) = 4.
match a with
| ANum n ⇒ n
| APlus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) + (aeval a2)
| AMinus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) - (aeval a2)
| AMult a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval a1) * (aeval a2)
end.
Example test_aeval1:
aeval (APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 2)) = 4.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Similarly, evaluating a boolean expression yields a boolean.
Fixpoint beval (b : bexp) : bool :=
match b with
| BTrue ⇒ true
| BFalse ⇒ false
| BEq a1 a2 ⇒ beq_nat (aeval a1) (aeval a2)
| BLe a1 a2 ⇒ leb (aeval a1) (aeval a2)
| BNot b1 ⇒ negb (beval b1)
| BAnd b1 b2 ⇒ andb (beval b1) (beval b2)
end.
match b with
| BTrue ⇒ true
| BFalse ⇒ false
| BEq a1 a2 ⇒ beq_nat (aeval a1) (aeval a2)
| BLe a1 a2 ⇒ leb (aeval a1) (aeval a2)
| BNot b1 ⇒ negb (beval b1)
| BAnd b1 b2 ⇒ andb (beval b1) (beval b2)
end.
Optimization
Fixpoint optimize_0plus (a:aexp) : aexp :=
match a with
| ANum n ⇒
ANum n
| APlus (ANum 0) e2 ⇒
optimize_0plus e2
| APlus e1 e2 ⇒
APlus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
| AMinus e1 e2 ⇒
AMinus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
| AMult e1 e2 ⇒
AMult (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
end.
match a with
| ANum n ⇒
ANum n
| APlus (ANum 0) e2 ⇒
optimize_0plus e2
| APlus e1 e2 ⇒
APlus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
| AMinus e1 e2 ⇒
AMinus (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
| AMult e1 e2 ⇒
AMult (optimize_0plus e1) (optimize_0plus e2)
end.
To make sure our optimization is doing the right thing we
can test it on some examples and see if the output looks OK.
Example test_optimize_0plus:
optimize_0plus (APlus (ANum 2)
(APlus (ANum 0)
(APlus (ANum 0) (ANum 1))))
= APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 1).
optimize_0plus (APlus (ANum 2)
(APlus (ANum 0)
(APlus (ANum 0) (ANum 1))))
= APlus (ANum 2) (ANum 1).
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
But if we want to be sure the optimization is correct —
i.e., that evaluating an optimized expression gives the same
result as the original — we should prove it.
Theorem optimize_0plus_sound: ∀ a,
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a. induction a.
- (* ANum *) reflexivity.
- (* APlus *) destruct a1.
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n.
* (* n = 0 *) simpl. apply IHa2.
* (* n <> 0 *) simpl. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = APlus a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = AMinus a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = AMult a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
- (* AMinus *)
simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
- (* AMult *)
simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. Qed.
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a. induction a.
- (* ANum *) reflexivity.
- (* APlus *) destruct a1.
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n.
* (* n = 0 *) simpl. apply IHa2.
* (* n <> 0 *) simpl. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = APlus a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = AMinus a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* a1 = AMult a1_1 a1_2 *)
simpl. simpl in IHa1. rewrite IHa1.
rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
- (* AMinus *)
simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity.
- (* AMult *)
simpl. rewrite IHa1. rewrite IHa2. reflexivity. Qed.
Coq Automation
Tacticals
The try Tactical
Theorem silly1 : ∀ ae, aeval ae = aeval ae.
Proof. try reflexivity. (* this just does reflexivity *) Qed.
Theorem silly2 : ∀ (P : Prop), P → P.
Proof.
intros P HP.
try reflexivity. (* just reflexivity would have failed *)
apply HP. (* we can still finish the proof in some other way *)
Qed.
Proof. try reflexivity. (* this just does reflexivity *) Qed.
Theorem silly2 : ∀ (P : Prop), P → P.
Proof.
intros P HP.
try reflexivity. (* just reflexivity would have failed *)
apply HP. (* we can still finish the proof in some other way *)
Qed.
There is no real reason to use try in completely manual
proofs like these, but it is very useful for doing automated
proofs in conjunction with the ; tactical, which we show
next.
The ; Tactical (Simple Form)
Lemma foo : ∀ n, leb 0 n = true.
Proof.
intros.
destruct n.
(* Leaves two subgoals, which are discharged identically... *)
- (* n=0 *) simpl. reflexivity.
- (* n=Sn' *) simpl. reflexivity.
Qed.
Proof.
intros.
destruct n.
(* Leaves two subgoals, which are discharged identically... *)
- (* n=0 *) simpl. reflexivity.
- (* n=Sn' *) simpl. reflexivity.
Qed.
We can simplify this proof using the ; tactical:
Lemma foo' : ∀ n, leb 0 n = true.
Proof.
intros.
(* destruct the current goal *)
destruct n;
(* then simpl each resulting subgoal *)
simpl;
(* and do reflexivity on each resulting subgoal *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
Proof.
intros.
(* destruct the current goal *)
destruct n;
(* then simpl each resulting subgoal *)
simpl;
(* and do reflexivity on each resulting subgoal *)
reflexivity.
Qed.
Using try and ; together, we can get rid of the repetition in
the proof that was bothering us a little while ago.
Theorem optimize_0plus_sound': ∀ a,
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a.
induction a;
(* Most cases follow directly by the IH... *)
try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
(* ... but the remaining cases -- ANum and APlus --
are different: *)
- (* ANum *) reflexivity.
- (* APlus *)
destruct a1;
(* Again, most cases follow directly by the IH: *)
try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1;
rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
(* The interesting case, on which the try...
does nothing, is when e1 = ANum n. In this
case, we have to destruct n (to see whether
the optimization applies) and rewrite with the
induction hypothesis. *)
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n;
simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed.
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a.
induction a;
(* Most cases follow directly by the IH... *)
try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
(* ... but the remaining cases -- ANum and APlus --
are different: *)
- (* ANum *) reflexivity.
- (* APlus *)
destruct a1;
(* Again, most cases follow directly by the IH: *)
try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1;
rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
(* The interesting case, on which the try...
does nothing, is when e1 = ANum n. In this
case, we have to destruct n (to see whether
the optimization applies) and rewrite with the
induction hypothesis. *)
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n;
simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed.
Coq experts often use this "...; try... " idiom after a tactic
like induction to take care of many similar cases all at once.
Naturally, this practice has an analog in informal proofs. For
example, here is an informal proof of the optimization theorem
that matches the structure of the formal one:
Theorem: For all arithmetic expressions a,
However, this proof can still be improved: the first case (for
a = ANum n) is very trivial — even more trivial than the cases
that we said simply followed from the IH — yet we have chosen to
write it out in full. It would be better and clearer to drop it
and just say, at the top, "Most cases are either immediate or
direct from the IH. The only interesting case is the one for
APlus..." We can make the same improvement in our formal proof
too. Here's how it looks:
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof: By induction on a. Most cases follow directly from the
IH. The remaining cases are as follows:
- Suppose a = ANum n for some n. We must show
aeval (optimize_0plus (ANum n)) = aeval (ANum n).This is immediate from the definition of optimize_0plus.
- Suppose a = APlus a1 a2 for some a1 and a2. We must
show
aeval (optimize_0plus (APlus a1 a2)) = aeval (APlus a1 a2).Consider the possible forms of a1. For most of them, optimize_0plus simply calls itself recursively for the subexpressions and rebuilds a new expression of the same form as a1; in these cases, the result follows directly from the IH.optimize_0plus (APlus a1 a2) = optimize_0plus a2and the IH for a2 is exactly what we need. On the other hand, if n = S n' for some n', then again optimize_0plus simply calls itself recursively, and the result follows from the IH. ☐
Theorem optimize_0plus_sound'': ∀ a,
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a.
induction a;
(* Most cases follow directly by the IH *)
try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity);
(* ... or are immediate by definition *)
try reflexivity.
(* The interesting case is when a = APlus a1 a2. *)
- (* APlus *)
destruct a1; try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1;
rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n;
simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed.
aeval (optimize_0plus a) = aeval a.
Proof.
intros a.
induction a;
(* Most cases follow directly by the IH *)
try (simpl; rewrite IHa1; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity);
(* ... or are immediate by definition *)
try reflexivity.
(* The interesting case is when a = APlus a1 a2. *)
- (* APlus *)
destruct a1; try (simpl; simpl in IHa1; rewrite IHa1;
rewrite IHa2; reflexivity).
+ (* a1 = ANum n *) destruct n;
simpl; rewrite IHa2; reflexivity. Qed.
The ; Tactical (General Form)
T; [T1 | T2 | ... | Tn]
is a tactic that first performs T and then performs T1 on the
first subgoal generated by T, performs T2 on the second
subgoal, etc.
T; [T' | T' | ... | T']
The repeat Tactical
The tactic repeat T never fails: if the tactic T doesn't apply
to the original goal, then repeat still succeeds without changing
the original goal (i.e., it repeats zero times).
Theorem In10' : In 10 [1;2;3;4;5;6;7;8;9;10].
Proof.
repeat (left; reflexivity).
repeat (right; try (left; reflexivity)).
Qed.
Proof.
repeat (left; reflexivity).
repeat (right; try (left; reflexivity)).
Qed.
The tactic repeat T also does not have any upper bound on the
number of times it applies T. If T is a tactic that always
succeeds, then repeat T will loop forever (e.g., repeat simpl
loops forever, since simpl always succeeds). While evaluation
in Coq's term language, Gallina, is guaranteed to terminate,
tactic evaluation is not! This does not affect Coq's logical
consistency, however, since the job of repeat and other tactics
is to guide Coq in constructing proofs; if the construction
process diverges, this simply means that we have failed to
construct a proof, not that we have constructed a wrong one.
Exercise: 3 stars (optimize_0plus_b)
Since the optimize_0plus transformation doesn't change the value of aexps, we should be able to apply it to all the aexps that appear in a bexp without changing the bexp's value. Write a function that performs this transformation on bexps and prove it is sound. Use the tacticals we've just seen to make the proof as elegant as possible.
Fixpoint optimize_0plus_b (b : bexp) : bexp
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Theorem optimize_0plus_b_sound : ∀ b,
beval (optimize_0plus_b b) = beval b.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Theorem optimize_0plus_b_sound : ∀ b,
beval (optimize_0plus_b b) = beval b.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (optimizer)
Design exercise: The optimization implemented by our optimize_0plus function is only one of many possible optimizations on arithmetic and boolean expressions. Write a more sophisticated optimizer and prove it correct. (You will probably find it easiest to start small — add just a single, simple optimization and prove it correct — and build up to something more interesting incrementially.)☐
Defining New Tactic Notations
- The Tactic Notation idiom illustrated below gives a handy way
to define "shorthand tactics" that bundle several tactics into a
single command.
- For more sophisticated programming, Coq offers a built-in
language called Ltac with primitives that can examine and
modify the proof state. The details are a bit too complicated
to get into here (and it is generally agreed that Ltac is not
the most beautiful part of Coq's design!), but they can be found
in the reference manual and other books on Coq, and there are
many examples of Ltac definitions in the Coq standard library
that you can use as examples.
- There is also an OCaml API, which can be used to build tactics that access Coq's internal structures at a lower level, but this is seldom worth the trouble for ordinary Coq users.
Tactic Notation "simpl_and_try" tactic(c) :=
simpl;
try c.
simpl;
try c.
This defines a new tactical called simpl_and_try that takes one
tactic c as an argument and is defined to be equivalent to the
tactic simpl; try c. Now writing "simpl_and_try reflexivity."
in a proof will be the same as writing "simpl; try
reflexivity."
The omega Tactic
- numeric constants, addition (+ and S), subtraction (-
and pred), and multiplication by constants (this is what
makes it Presburger arithmetic),
- equality (= and ≠) and ordering (≤), and
- the logical connectives ∧, ∨, ¬, and →,
Example silly_presburger_example : ∀ m n o p,
m + n ≤ n + o ∧ o + 3 = p + 3 →
m ≤ p.
Proof.
intros. omega.
Qed.
m + n ≤ n + o ∧ o + 3 = p + 3 →
m ≤ p.
Proof.
intros. omega.
Qed.
(Note the Require Import Coq.omega.Omega. at the top of
the file.)
A Few More Handy Tactics
- clear H: Delete hypothesis H from the context.
- subst x: Find an assumption x = e or e = x in the
context, replace x with e throughout the context and
current goal, and clear the assumption.
- subst: Substitute away all assumptions of the form x = e
or e = x.
- rename... into...: Change the name of a hypothesis in the
proof context. For example, if the context includes a variable
named x, then rename x into y will change all occurrences
of x to y.
- assumption: Try to find a hypothesis H in the context that
exactly matches the goal; if one is found, behave like apply
H.
- contradiction: Try to find a hypothesis H in the current
context that is logically equivalent to False. If one is
found, solve the goal.
- constructor: Try to find a constructor c (from some Inductive definition in the current environment) that can be applied to solve the current goal. If one is found, behave like apply c.
Evaluation as a Relation
Module aevalR_first_try.
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n: nat),
aevalR (ANum n) n
| E_APlus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus: ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (AMinus e1 e2) (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (AMult e1 e2) (n1 * n2).
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n: nat),
aevalR (ANum n) n
| E_APlus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus: ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (AMinus e1 e2) (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (AMult e1 e2) (n1 * n2).
It will be convenient to have an infix notation for
aevalR. We'll write e \\ n to mean that arithmetic expression
e evaluates to value n.
Notation "e '\\' n"
:= (aevalR e n)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: type_scope.
End aevalR_first_try.
:= (aevalR e n)
(at level 50, left associativity)
: type_scope.
End aevalR_first_try.
In fact, Coq provides a way to use this notation in the
definition of aevalR itself. This reduces confusion by avoiding
situations where we're working on a proof involving statements in
the form e \\ n but we have to refer back to a definition
written using the form aevalR e n.
We do this by first "reserving" the notation, then giving the
definition together with a declaration of what the notation
means.
Reserved Notation "e '\\' n" (at level 50, left associativity).
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (APlus e1 e2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (AMinus e1 e2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (AMult e1 e2) \\ (n1 * n2)
where "e '\\' n" := (aevalR e n) : type_scope.
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (APlus e1 e2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (AMinus e1 e2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(e1 \\ n1) → (e2 \\ n2) → (AMult e1 e2) \\ (n1 * n2)
where "e '\\' n" := (aevalR e n) : type_scope.
Inference Rule Notation
| E_APlus : ∀ (e1 e2: aexp) (n1 n2: nat),
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2)
...would be written like this as an inference rule:
aevalR e1 n1 →
aevalR e2 n2 →
aevalR (APlus e1 e2) (n1 + n2)
e1 \\ n1 | |
e2 \\ n2 | (E_APlus) |
APlus e1 e2 \\ n1+n2 |
(E_ANum) | |
ANum n \\ n |
e1 \\ n1 | |
e2 \\ n2 | (E_APlus) |
APlus e1 e2 \\ n1+n2 |
e1 \\ n1 | |
e2 \\ n2 | (E_AMinus) |
AMinus e1 e2 \\ n1-n2 |
e1 \\ n1 | |
e2 \\ n2 | (E_AMult) |
AMult e1 e2 \\ n1*n2 |
Equivalence of the Definitions
Theorem aeval_iff_aevalR : ∀ a n,
(a \\ n) ↔ aeval a = n.
(a \\ n) ↔ aeval a = n.
Proof.
split.
- (* -> *)
intros H.
induction H; simpl.
+ (* E_ANum *)
reflexivity.
+ (* E_APlus *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
+ (* E_AMinus *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
+ (* E_AMult *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
- (* <- *)
generalize dependent n.
induction a;
simpl; intros; subst.
+ (* ANum *)
apply E_ANum.
+ (* APlus *)
apply E_APlus.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* AMinus *)
apply E_AMinus.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* AMult *)
apply E_AMult.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
Qed.
split.
- (* -> *)
intros H.
induction H; simpl.
+ (* E_ANum *)
reflexivity.
+ (* E_APlus *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
+ (* E_AMinus *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
+ (* E_AMult *)
rewrite IHaevalR1. rewrite IHaevalR2. reflexivity.
- (* <- *)
generalize dependent n.
induction a;
simpl; intros; subst.
+ (* ANum *)
apply E_ANum.
+ (* APlus *)
apply E_APlus.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* AMinus *)
apply E_AMinus.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
+ (* AMult *)
apply E_AMult.
apply IHa1. reflexivity.
apply IHa2. reflexivity.
Qed.
We can make the proof quite a bit shorter by making more
use of tacticals.
Theorem aeval_iff_aevalR' : ∀ a n,
(a \\ n) ↔ aeval a = n.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
split.
- (* -> *)
intros H; induction H; subst; reflexivity.
- (* <- *)
generalize dependent n.
induction a; simpl; intros; subst; constructor;
try apply IHa1; try apply IHa2; reflexivity.
Qed.
(a \\ n) ↔ aeval a = n.
Proof.
(* WORKED IN CLASS *)
split.
- (* -> *)
intros H; induction H; subst; reflexivity.
- (* <- *)
generalize dependent n.
induction a; simpl; intros; subst; constructor;
try apply IHa1; try apply IHa2; reflexivity.
Qed.
Exercise: 3 stars (bevalR)
Write a relation bevalR in the same style as aevalR, and prove that it is equivalent to beval.
Inductive bevalR: bexp → bool → Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Lemma beval_iff_bevalR : ∀ b bv,
bevalR b bv ↔ beval b = bv.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Lemma beval_iff_bevalR : ∀ b bv,
bevalR b bv ↔ beval b = bv.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Computational vs. Relational Definitions
For example, suppose that we wanted to extend the arithmetic
operations by considering also a division operation:
Inductive aexp : Type :=
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp
| ADiv : aexp → aexp → aexp. (* <--- new *)
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp
| ADiv : aexp → aexp → aexp. (* <--- new *)
Extending the definition of aeval to handle this new operation
would not be straightforward (what should we return as the result
of ADiv (ANum 5) (ANum 0)?). But extending aevalR is
straightforward.
Reserved Notation "e '\\' n"
(at level 50, left associativity).
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (APlus a1 a2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMinus a1 a2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMult a1 a2) \\ (n1 * n2)
| E_ADiv : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 n3: nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (n2 > 0) →
(mult n2 n3 = n1) → (ADiv a1 a2) \\ n3
where "a '\\' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope.
End aevalR_division.
Module aevalR_extended.
(at level 50, left associativity).
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (APlus a1 a2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMinus a1 a2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMult a1 a2) \\ (n1 * n2)
| E_ADiv : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 n3: nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (n2 > 0) →
(mult n2 n3 = n1) → (ADiv a1 a2) \\ n3
where "a '\\' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope.
End aevalR_division.
Module aevalR_extended.
Suppose, instead, that we want to extend the arithmetic operations
by a nondeterministic number generator any that, when evaluated,
may yield any number. (Note that this is not the same as making a
probabilistic choice among all possible numbers — we're not
specifying any particular distribution of results, but just saying
what results are possible.)
Reserved Notation "e '\\' n" (at level 50, left associativity).
Inductive aexp : Type :=
| AAny : aexp (* <--- NEW *)
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
Inductive aexp : Type :=
| AAny : aexp (* <--- NEW *)
| ANum : nat → aexp
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
Again, extending aeval would be tricky, since now evaluation is
not a deterministic function from expressions to numbers, but
extending aevalR is no problem...
Inductive aevalR : aexp → nat → Prop :=
| E_Any : ∀ (n:nat),
AAny \\ n (* <--- new *)
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (APlus a1 a2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMinus a1 a2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMult a1 a2) \\ (n1 * n2)
where "a '\\' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope.
End aevalR_extended.
| E_Any : ∀ (n:nat),
AAny \\ n (* <--- new *)
| E_ANum : ∀ (n:nat),
(ANum n) \\ n
| E_APlus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (APlus a1 a2) \\ (n1 + n2)
| E_AMinus : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMinus a1 a2) \\ (n1 - n2)
| E_AMult : ∀ (a1 a2: aexp) (n1 n2 : nat),
(a1 \\ n1) → (a2 \\ n2) → (AMult a1 a2) \\ (n1 * n2)
where "a '\\' n" := (aevalR a n) : type_scope.
End aevalR_extended.
At this point you maybe wondering: which style should I use by
default? The examples above show that relational definitions are
fundamentally more powerful than functional ones. For situations
like these, where the thing being defined is not easy to express
as a function, or indeed where it is not a function, there is no
choice. But what about when both styles are workable?
One point in favor of relational definitions is that some people
feel they are more elegant and easier to understand. Another is
that Coq automatically generates nice inversion and induction
principles from Inductive definitions.
On the other hand, functional definitions can often be more
convenient:
Furthermore, functions can be directly "extracted" to executable
code in OCaml or Haskell.
Ultimately, the choice often comes down to either the specifics of
a particular situation or simply a question of taste. Indeed, in
large Coq developments it is common to see a definition given in
both functional and relational styles, plus a lemma stating that
the two coincide, allowing further proofs to switch from one point
of view to the other at will.
- Functions are by definition deterministic and defined on all arguments; for a relation we have to show these properties explicitly if we need them.
- With functions we can also take advantage of Coq's computation mechanism to simplify expressions during proofs.
Expressions With Variables
States
Syntax
Inductive aexp : Type :=
| ANum : nat → aexp
| AId : string → aexp (* <----- NEW *)
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
| ANum : nat → aexp
| AId : string → aexp (* <----- NEW *)
| APlus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMinus : aexp → aexp → aexp
| AMult : aexp → aexp → aexp.
Defining a few variable names as notational shorthands will make
examples easier to read:
Definition W : string := "W".
Definition X : string := "X".
Definition Y : string := "Y".
Definition Z : string := "Z".
Definition X : string := "X".
Definition Y : string := "Y".
Definition Z : string := "Z".
(This convention for naming program variables (X, Y,
Z) clashes a bit with our earlier use of uppercase letters for
types. Since we're not using polymorphism heavily in the chapters
developed to Imp, this overloading should not cause confusion.)
The definition of bexps is unchanged (except that it now refers
to the new aexps):
Inductive bexp : Type :=
| BTrue : bexp
| BFalse : bexp
| BEq : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BLe : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BNot : bexp → bexp
| BAnd : bexp → bexp → bexp.
| BTrue : bexp
| BFalse : bexp
| BEq : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BLe : aexp → aexp → bexp
| BNot : bexp → bexp
| BAnd : bexp → bexp → bexp.
Notations
To make Imp programs easier to read and write, we introduce some notations and implicit coercions.
Coercion AId : string >-> aexp.
Coercion ANum : nat >-> aexp.
Definition bool_to_bexp (b: bool) : bexp :=
if b then BTrue else BFalse.
Coercion bool_to_bexp : bool >-> bexp.
Bind Scope aexp_scope with aexp.
Infix "+" := APlus : aexp_scope.
Infix "-" := AMinus : aexp_scope.
Infix "*" := AMult : aexp_scope.
Bind Scope bexp_scope with bexp.
Infix "≤" := BLe : bexp_scope.
Infix "=" := BEq : bexp_scope.
Infix "&&" := BAnd : bexp_scope.
Notation "'!' b" := (BNot b) (at level 60) : bexp_scope.
Coercion ANum : nat >-> aexp.
Definition bool_to_bexp (b: bool) : bexp :=
if b then BTrue else BFalse.
Coercion bool_to_bexp : bool >-> bexp.
Bind Scope aexp_scope with aexp.
Infix "+" := APlus : aexp_scope.
Infix "-" := AMinus : aexp_scope.
Infix "*" := AMult : aexp_scope.
Bind Scope bexp_scope with bexp.
Infix "≤" := BLe : bexp_scope.
Infix "=" := BEq : bexp_scope.
Infix "&&" := BAnd : bexp_scope.
Notation "'!' b" := (BNot b) (at level 60) : bexp_scope.
We can now write 3 + (X * 2) instead of APlus 3 (AMult X 2),
and true && !(X ≤ 4) instead of BAnd true (BNot (BLe X 4)).
Evaluation
Fixpoint aeval (st : state) (a : aexp) : nat :=
match a with
| ANum n ⇒ n
| AId x ⇒ st x (* <----- NEW *)
| APlus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) + (aeval st a2)
| AMinus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) - (aeval st a2)
| AMult a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) * (aeval st a2)
end.
Fixpoint beval (st : state) (b : bexp) : bool :=
match b with
| BTrue ⇒ true
| BFalse ⇒ false
| BEq a1 a2 ⇒ beq_nat (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2)
| BLe a1 a2 ⇒ leb (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2)
| BNot b1 ⇒ negb (beval st b1)
| BAnd b1 b2 ⇒ andb (beval st b1) (beval st b2)
end.
match a with
| ANum n ⇒ n
| AId x ⇒ st x (* <----- NEW *)
| APlus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) + (aeval st a2)
| AMinus a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) - (aeval st a2)
| AMult a1 a2 ⇒ (aeval st a1) * (aeval st a2)
end.
Fixpoint beval (st : state) (b : bexp) : bool :=
match b with
| BTrue ⇒ true
| BFalse ⇒ false
| BEq a1 a2 ⇒ beq_nat (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2)
| BLe a1 a2 ⇒ leb (aeval st a1) (aeval st a2)
| BNot b1 ⇒ negb (beval st b1)
| BAnd b1 b2 ⇒ andb (beval st b1) (beval st b2)
end.
We specialize our notation for total maps to the specific case of states,
i.e. using { --> 0 } as empty state.
Notation "{ a --> x }" :=
(t_update { --> 0 } a x) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x }) b y) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y }) c z) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z }) d t) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t }) e u) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u ; f --> v }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u }) f v) (at level 0).
Example aexp1 :
aeval { X --> 5 } (3 + (X * 2))
= 13.
Example bexp1 :
beval { X --> 5 } (true && !(X ≤ 4))
= true.
(t_update { --> 0 } a x) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x }) b y) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y }) c z) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z }) d t) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t }) e u) (at level 0).
Notation "{ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u ; f --> v }" :=
(t_update ({ a --> x ; b --> y ; c --> z ; d --> t ; e --> u }) f v) (at level 0).
Example aexp1 :
aeval { X --> 5 } (3 + (X * 2))
= 13.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Example bexp1 :
beval { X --> 5 } (true && !(X ≤ 4))
= true.
Proof. reflexivity. Qed.
Commands
Syntax
c ::= SKIP | x ::= a | c ;; c | IFB b THEN c ELSE c FI
| WHILE b DO c END
| WHILE b DO c END
Z ::= X;;
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
When this command terminates, the variable Y will contain the
factorial of the initial value of X.
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END
Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CAss : string → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com.
| CSkip : com
| CAss : string → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com.
As for expressions, we can use a few Notation declarations to make
reading and writing Imp programs more convenient.
Bind Scope com_scope with com.
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip : com_scope.
Notation "x '::=' a" :=
(CAss x a) (at level 60) : com_scope.
Notation "c1 ;; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" :=
(CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip : com_scope.
Notation "x '::=' a" :=
(CAss x a) (at level 60) : com_scope.
Notation "c1 ;; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" :=
(CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity) : com_scope.
The following declaration is needed to be able to use the
notations in match patterns.
Open Scope com_scope.
For example, here is the factorial function again, written as a
formal definition to Coq:
Definition fact_in_coq : com :=
Z ::= X;;
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END.
Z ::= X;;
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE ! (Z = 0) DO
Y ::= Y * Z;;
Z ::= Z - 1
END.
Definition plus2 : com :=
X ::= X + 2.
Definition XtimesYinZ : com :=
Z ::= X * Y.
Definition subtract_slowly_body : com :=
Z ::= Z - 1 ;;
X ::= X - 1.
X ::= X + 2.
Definition XtimesYinZ : com :=
Z ::= X * Y.
Definition subtract_slowly_body : com :=
Z ::= Z - 1 ;;
X ::= X - 1.
Definition subtract_slowly : com :=
WHILE ! (X = 0) DO
subtract_slowly_body
END.
Definition subtract_3_from_5_slowly : com :=
X ::= 3 ;;
Z ::= 5 ;;
subtract_slowly.
Evaluating Commands
Evaluation as a Function (Failed Attempt)
Fixpoint ceval_fun_no_while (st : state) (c : com)
: state :=
match c with
| SKIP ⇒
st
| x ::= a1 ⇒
st & { x --> (aeval st a1) }
| c1 ;; c2 ⇒
let st' := ceval_fun_no_while st c1 in
ceval_fun_no_while st' c2
| IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI ⇒
if (beval st b)
then ceval_fun_no_while st c1
else ceval_fun_no_while st c2
| WHILE b DO c END ⇒
st (* bogus *)
end.
: state :=
match c with
| SKIP ⇒
st
| x ::= a1 ⇒
st & { x --> (aeval st a1) }
| c1 ;; c2 ⇒
let st' := ceval_fun_no_while st c1 in
ceval_fun_no_while st' c2
| IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI ⇒
if (beval st b)
then ceval_fun_no_while st c1
else ceval_fun_no_while st c2
| WHILE b DO c END ⇒
st (* bogus *)
end.
In a traditional functional programming language like OCaml or
Haskell we could add the WHILE case as follows:
Thus, because it doesn't terminate on all inputs,
of ceval_fun cannot be written in Coq — at least not without
additional tricks and workarounds (see chapter ImpCEvalFun
if you're curious about what those might be).
Fixpoint ceval_fun (st : state) (c : com) : state := match c with ... | WHILE b DO c END => if (beval st b) then ceval_fun st (c; WHILE b DO c END) else st end.Coq doesn't accept such a definition ("Error: Cannot guess decreasing argument of fix") because the function we want to define is not guaranteed to terminate. Indeed, it doesn't always terminate: for example, the full version of the ceval_fun function applied to the loop program above would never terminate. Since Coq is not just a functional programming language but also a consistent logic, any potentially non-terminating function needs to be rejected. Here is an (invalid!) program showing what would go wrong if Coq allowed non-terminating recursive functions:
Fixpoint loop_false (n : nat) : False := loop_false n.That is, propositions like False would become provable (loop_false 0 would be a proof of False), which would be a disaster for Coq's logical consistency.
Evaluation as a Relation
Operational Semantics
(E_Skip) | |
SKIP / st \\ st |
aeval st a1 = n | (E_Ass) |
x := a1 / st \\ st & { x --> n } |
c1 / st \\ st' | |
c2 / st' \\ st'' | (E_Seq) |
c1;;c2 / st \\ st'' |
beval st b1 = true | |
c1 / st \\ st' | (E_IfTrue) |
IF b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st \\ st' |
beval st b1 = false | |
c2 / st \\ st' | (E_IfFalse) |
IF b1 THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st \\ st' |
beval st b = false | (E_WhileFalse) |
WHILE b DO c END / st \\ st |
beval st b = true | |
c / st \\ st' | |
WHILE b DO c END / st' \\ st'' | (E_WhileTrue) |
WHILE b DO c END / st \\ st'' |
Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '\\' st'"
(at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive ceval : com → state → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀ st,
SKIP / st \\ st
| E_Ass : ∀ st a1 n x,
aeval st a1 = n →
(x ::= a1) / st \\ st & { x --> n }
| E_Seq : ∀ c1 c2 st st' st'',
c1 / st \\ st' →
c2 / st' \\ st'' →
(c1 ;; c2) / st \\ st''
| E_IfTrue : ∀ st st' b c1 c2,
beval st b = true →
c1 / st \\ st' →
(IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st \\ st'
| E_IfFalse : ∀ st st' b c1 c2,
beval st b = false →
c2 / st \\ st' →
(IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st \\ st'
| E_WhileFalse : ∀ b st c,
beval st b = false →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ st
| E_WhileTrue : ∀ st st' st'' b c,
beval st b = true →
c / st \\ st' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st' \\ st'' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ st''
where "c1 '/' st '\\' st'" := (ceval c1 st st').
(at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive ceval : com → state → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀ st,
SKIP / st \\ st
| E_Ass : ∀ st a1 n x,
aeval st a1 = n →
(x ::= a1) / st \\ st & { x --> n }
| E_Seq : ∀ c1 c2 st st' st'',
c1 / st \\ st' →
c2 / st' \\ st'' →
(c1 ;; c2) / st \\ st''
| E_IfTrue : ∀ st st' b c1 c2,
beval st b = true →
c1 / st \\ st' →
(IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st \\ st'
| E_IfFalse : ∀ st st' b c1 c2,
beval st b = false →
c2 / st \\ st' →
(IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st \\ st'
| E_WhileFalse : ∀ b st c,
beval st b = false →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ st
| E_WhileTrue : ∀ st st' st'' b c,
beval st b = true →
c / st \\ st' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st' \\ st'' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ st''
where "c1 '/' st '\\' st'" := (ceval c1 st st').
The cost of defining evaluation as a relation instead of a
function is that we now need to construct proofs that some
program evaluates to some result state, rather than just letting
Coq's computation mechanism do it for us.
Example ceval_example1:
(X ::= 2;;
IFB X ≤ 1
THEN Y ::= 3
ELSE Z ::= 4
FI)
/ { --> 0 } \\ { X --> 2 ; Z --> 4 }.
Proof.
(* We must supply the intermediate state *)
apply E_Seq with { X --> 2 }.
- (* assignment command *)
apply E_Ass. reflexivity.
- (* if command *)
apply E_IfFalse.
reflexivity.
apply E_Ass. reflexivity. Qed.
(X ::= 2;;
IFB X ≤ 1
THEN Y ::= 3
ELSE Z ::= 4
FI)
/ { --> 0 } \\ { X --> 2 ; Z --> 4 }.
Proof.
(* We must supply the intermediate state *)
apply E_Seq with { X --> 2 }.
- (* assignment command *)
apply E_Ass. reflexivity.
- (* if command *)
apply E_IfFalse.
reflexivity.
apply E_Ass. reflexivity. Qed.
Example ceval_example2:
(X ::= 0;; Y ::= 1;; Z ::= 2) / { --> 0 } \\
{ X --> 0 ; Y --> 1 ; Z --> 2 }.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(X ::= 0;; Y ::= 1;; Z ::= 2) / { --> 0 } \\
{ X --> 0 ; Y --> 1 ; Z --> 2 }.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (pup_to_n)
Write an Imp program that sums the numbers from 1 to X (inclusive: 1 + 2 + ... + X) in the variable Y. Prove that this program executes as intended for X = 2 (this is trickier than you might expect).
Definition pup_to_n : com
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Theorem pup_to_2_ceval :
pup_to_n / { X --> 2 }
\\ { X --> 2 ; Y --> 0 ; Y --> 2 ; X --> 1 ; Y --> 3 ; X --> 0 }.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Theorem pup_to_2_ceval :
pup_to_n / { X --> 2 }
\\ { X --> 2 ; Y --> 0 ; Y --> 2 ; X --> 1 ; Y --> 3 ; X --> 0 }.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Determinism of Evaluation
Theorem ceval_deterministic: ∀ c st st1 st2,
c / st \\ st1 →
c / st \\ st2 →
st1 = st2.
c / st \\ st1 →
c / st \\ st2 →
st1 = st2.
Proof.
intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2.
generalize dependent st2.
induction E1;
intros st2 E2; inversion E2; subst.
- (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Ass *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Seq *)
assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
subst st'0.
apply IHE1_2. assumption.
- (* E_IfTrue, b1 evaluates to true *)
apply IHE1. assumption.
- (* E_IfTrue, b1 evaluates to false (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
- (* E_IfFalse, b1 evaluates to true (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
- (* E_IfFalse, b1 evaluates to false *)
apply IHE1. assumption.
- (* E_WhileFalse, b1 evaluates to false *)
reflexivity.
- (* E_WhileFalse, b1 evaluates to true (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H2. inversion H2.
- (* E_WhileTrue, b1 evaluates to false (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H4. inversion H4.
- (* E_WhileTrue, b1 evaluates to true *)
assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
subst st'0.
apply IHE1_2. assumption. Qed.
intros c st st1 st2 E1 E2.
generalize dependent st2.
induction E1;
intros st2 E2; inversion E2; subst.
- (* E_Skip *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Ass *) reflexivity.
- (* E_Seq *)
assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
subst st'0.
apply IHE1_2. assumption.
- (* E_IfTrue, b1 evaluates to true *)
apply IHE1. assumption.
- (* E_IfTrue, b1 evaluates to false (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
- (* E_IfFalse, b1 evaluates to true (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H5. inversion H5.
- (* E_IfFalse, b1 evaluates to false *)
apply IHE1. assumption.
- (* E_WhileFalse, b1 evaluates to false *)
reflexivity.
- (* E_WhileFalse, b1 evaluates to true (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H2. inversion H2.
- (* E_WhileTrue, b1 evaluates to false (contradiction) *)
rewrite H in H4. inversion H4.
- (* E_WhileTrue, b1 evaluates to true *)
assert (st' = st'0) as EQ1.
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply IHE1_1; assumption. }
subst st'0.
apply IHE1_2. assumption. Qed.
Reasoning About Imp Programs
Theorem plus2_spec : ∀ st n st',
st X = n →
plus2 / st \\ st' →
st' X = (n + 2).
Proof.
intros st n st' HX Heval.
st X = n →
plus2 / st \\ st' →
st' X = (n + 2).
Proof.
intros st n st' HX Heval.
Inverting Heval essentially forces Coq to expand one step of
the ceval computation — in this case revealing that st'
must be st extended with the new value of X, since plus2
is an assignment
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Theorem loop_never_stops : ∀ st st',
~(loop / st \\ st').
Proof.
intros st st' contra. unfold loop in contra.
remember (WHILE true DO SKIP END) as loopdef
eqn:Heqloopdef.
~(loop / st \\ st').
Proof.
intros st st' contra. unfold loop in contra.
remember (WHILE true DO SKIP END) as loopdef
eqn:Heqloopdef.
Proceed by induction on the assumed derivation showing that
loopdef terminates. Most of the cases are immediately
contradictory (and so can be solved in one step with
inversion).
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Fixpoint no_whiles (c : com) : bool :=
match c with
| SKIP ⇒
true
| _ ::= _ ⇒
true
| c1 ;; c2 ⇒
andb (no_whiles c1) (no_whiles c2)
| IFB _ THEN ct ELSE cf FI ⇒
andb (no_whiles ct) (no_whiles cf)
| WHILE _ DO _ END ⇒
false
end.
match c with
| SKIP ⇒
true
| _ ::= _ ⇒
true
| c1 ;; c2 ⇒
andb (no_whiles c1) (no_whiles c2)
| IFB _ THEN ct ELSE cf FI ⇒
andb (no_whiles ct) (no_whiles cf)
| WHILE _ DO _ END ⇒
false
end.
This predicate yields true just on programs that have no while
loops. Using Inductive, write a property no_whilesR such that
no_whilesR c is provable exactly when c is a program with no
while loops. Then prove its equivalence with no_whiles.
Inductive no_whilesR: com → Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Theorem no_whiles_eqv:
∀ c, no_whiles c = true ↔ no_whilesR c.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* FILL IN HERE *)
.
Theorem no_whiles_eqv:
∀ c, no_whiles c = true ↔ no_whilesR c.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 4 stars (no_whiles_terminating)
Imp programs that don't involve while loops always terminate. State and prove a theorem no_whiles_terminating that says this. Use either no_whiles or no_whilesR, as you prefer.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Additional Exercises
Exercise: 3 stars (stack_compiler)
Old HP Calculators, programming languages like Forth and Postscript, and abstract machines like the Java Virtual Machine all evaluate arithmetic expressions using a stack. For instance, the expression(2*3)+(3*(4-2))would be written as
2 3 * 3 4 2 - * +and evaluated like this (where we show the program being evaluated on the right and the contents of the stack on the left):
[ ] | 2 3 * 3 4 2 - * + [2] | 3 * 3 4 2 - * + [3, 2] | * 3 4 2 - * + [6] | 3 4 2 - * + [3, 6] | 4 2 - * + [4, 3, 6] | 2 - * + [2, 4, 3, 6] | - * + [2, 3, 6] | * + [6, 6] | + [12] |The goal of this exercise is to write a small compiler that translates aexps into stack machine instructions.
- SPush n: Push the number n on the stack.
- SLoad x: Load the identifier x from the store and push it on the stack
- SPlus: Pop the two top numbers from the stack, add them, and push the result onto the stack.
- SMinus: Similar, but subtract.
- SMult: Similar, but multiply.
Inductive sinstr : Type :=
| SPush : nat → sinstr
| SLoad : string → sinstr
| SPlus : sinstr
| SMinus : sinstr
| SMult : sinstr.
| SPush : nat → sinstr
| SLoad : string → sinstr
| SPlus : sinstr
| SMinus : sinstr
| SMult : sinstr.
Write a function to evaluate programs in the stack language. It
should take as input a state, a stack represented as a list of
numbers (top stack item is the head of the list), and a program
represented as a list of instructions, and it should return the
stack after executing the program. Test your function on the
examples below.
Note that the specification leaves unspecified what to do when
encountering an SPlus, SMinus, or SMult instruction if the
stack contains less than two elements. In a sense, it is
immaterial what we do, since our compiler will never emit such a
malformed program.
Fixpoint s_execute (st : state) (stack : list nat)
(prog : list sinstr)
: list nat
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Example s_execute1 :
s_execute { --> 0 } []
[SPush 5; SPush 3; SPush 1; SMinus]
= [2; 5].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example s_execute2 :
s_execute { X --> 3 } [3;4]
[SPush 4; SLoad X; SMult; SPlus]
= [15; 4].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(prog : list sinstr)
: list nat
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
Example s_execute1 :
s_execute { --> 0 } []
[SPush 5; SPush 3; SPush 1; SMinus]
= [2; 5].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Example s_execute2 :
s_execute { X --> 3 } [3;4]
[SPush 4; SLoad X; SMult; SPlus]
= [15; 4].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Next, write a function that compiles an aexp into a stack
machine program. The effect of running the program should be the
same as pushing the value of the expression on the stack.
Fixpoint s_compile (e : aexp) : list sinstr
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
(* REPLACE THIS LINE WITH ":= _your_definition_ ." *). Admitted.
After you've defined s_compile, prove the following to test
that it works.
Example s_compile1 :
s_compile (X - (2 * Y))
= [SLoad X; SPush 2; SLoad Y; SMult; SMinus].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
s_compile (X - (2 * Y))
= [SLoad X; SPush 2; SLoad Y; SMult; SMinus].
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 4 stars, advanced (stack_compiler_correct)
Now we'll prove the correctness of the compiler implemented in the previous exercise. Remember that the specification left unspecified what to do when encountering an SPlus, SMinus, or SMult instruction if the stack contains less than two elements. (In order to make your correctness proof easier you might find it helpful to go back and change your implementation!)
Theorem s_compile_correct : ∀ (st : state) (e : aexp),
s_execute st [] (s_compile e) = [ aeval st e ].
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
s_execute st [] (s_compile e) = [ aeval st e ].
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (short_circuit)
Most modern programming languages use a "short-circuit" evaluation rule for boolean and: to evaluate BAnd b1 b2, first evaluate b1. If it evaluates to false, then the entire BAnd expression evaluates to false immediately, without evaluating b2. Otherwise, b2 is evaluated to determine the result of the BAnd expression.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 4 stars, advanced (break_imp)
Imperative languages like C and Java often include a break or similar statement for interrupting the execution of loops. In this exercise we consider how to add break to Imp. First, we need to enrich the language of commands with an additional case.
Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CBreak : com (* <-- new *)
| CAss : string → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com.
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "'BREAK'" :=
CBreak.
Notation "x '::=' a" :=
(CAss x a) (at level 60).
Notation "c1 ;; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" :=
(CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity).
| CSkip : com
| CBreak : com (* <-- new *)
| CAss : string → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com.
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "'BREAK'" :=
CBreak.
Notation "x '::=' a" :=
(CAss x a) (at level 60).
Notation "c1 ;; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' c1 'THEN' c2 'ELSE' c3 'FI'" :=
(CIf c1 c2 c3) (at level 80, right associativity).
Next, we need to define the behavior of BREAK. Informally,
whenever BREAK is executed in a sequence of commands, it stops
the execution of that sequence and signals that the innermost
enclosing loop should terminate. (If there aren't any
enclosing loops, then the whole program simply terminates.) The
final state should be the same as the one in which the BREAK
statement was executed.
One important point is what to do when there are multiple loops
enclosing a given BREAK. In those cases, BREAK should only
terminate the innermost loop. Thus, after executing the
following...
One way of expressing this behavior is to add another parameter to
the evaluation relation that specifies whether evaluation of a
command executes a BREAK statement:
X ::= 0;;
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE 0 ≠ Y DO
WHILE TRUE DO
BREAK
END;;
X ::= 1;;
Y ::= Y - 1
END
... the value of X should be 1, and not 0.
Y ::= 1;;
WHILE 0 ≠ Y DO
WHILE TRUE DO
BREAK
END;;
X ::= 1;;
Y ::= Y - 1
END
Inductive result : Type :=
| SContinue : result
| SBreak : result.
Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '\\' s '/' st'"
(at level 40, st, s at level 39).
| SContinue : result
| SBreak : result.
Reserved Notation "c1 '/' st '\\' s '/' st'"
(at level 40, st, s at level 39).
Intuitively, c / st \\ s / st' means that, if c is started in
state st, then it terminates in state st' and either signals
that the innermost surrounding loop (or the whole program) should
exit immediately (s = SBreak) or that execution should continue
normally (s = SContinue).
The definition of the "c / st \\ s / st'" relation is very
similar to the one we gave above for the regular evaluation
relation (c / st \\ st') — we just need to handle the
termination signals appropriately:
Based on the above description, complete the definition of the
ceval relation.
- If the command is SKIP, then the state doesn't change and
execution of any enclosing loop can continue normally.
- If the command is BREAK, the state stays unchanged but we
signal a SBreak.
- If the command is an assignment, then we update the binding for
that variable in the state accordingly and signal that execution
can continue normally.
- If the command is of the form IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI, then
the state is updated as in the original semantics of Imp, except
that we also propagate the signal from the execution of
whichever branch was taken.
- If the command is a sequence c1 ;; c2, we first execute
c1. If this yields a SBreak, we skip the execution of c2
and propagate the SBreak signal to the surrounding context;
the resulting state is the same as the one obtained by
executing c1 alone. Otherwise, we execute c2 on the state
obtained after executing c1, and propagate the signal
generated there.
- Finally, for a loop of the form WHILE b DO c END, the semantics is almost the same as before. The only difference is that, when b evaluates to true, we execute c and check the signal that it raises. If that signal is SContinue, then the execution proceeds as in the original semantics. Otherwise, we stop the execution of the loop, and the resulting state is the same as the one resulting from the execution of the current iteration. In either case, since BREAK only terminates the innermost loop, WHILE signals SContinue.
Inductive ceval : com → state → result → state → Prop :=
| E_Skip : ∀ st,
CSkip / st \\ SContinue / st
(* FILL IN HERE *)
where "c1 '/' st '\\' s '/' st'" := (ceval c1 st s st').
| E_Skip : ∀ st,
CSkip / st \\ SContinue / st
(* FILL IN HERE *)
where "c1 '/' st '\\' s '/' st'" := (ceval c1 st s st').
Now prove the following properties of your definition of ceval:
Theorem break_ignore : ∀ c st st' s,
(BREAK;; c) / st \\ s / st' →
st = st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem while_continue : ∀ b c st st' s,
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ s / st' →
s = SContinue.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem while_stops_on_break : ∀ b c st st',
beval st b = true →
c / st \\ SBreak / st' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ SContinue / st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(BREAK;; c) / st \\ s / st' →
st = st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem while_continue : ∀ b c st st' s,
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ s / st' →
s = SContinue.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem while_stops_on_break : ∀ b c st st',
beval st b = true →
c / st \\ SBreak / st' →
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ SContinue / st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem while_break_true : ∀ b c st st',
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ SContinue / st' →
beval st' b = true →
∃ st'', c / st'' \\ SBreak / st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(WHILE b DO c END) / st \\ SContinue / st' →
beval st' b = true →
∃ st'', c / st'' \\ SBreak / st'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Theorem ceval_deterministic: ∀ (c:com) st st1 st2 s1 s2,
c / st \\ s1 / st1 →
c / st \\ s2 / st2 →
st1 = st2 ∧ s1 = s2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
c / st \\ s1 / st1 →
c / st \\ s2 / st2 →
st1 = st2 ∧ s1 = s2.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Exercise: 4 stars, optional (add_for_loop)
Add C-style for loops to the language of commands, update the ceval definition to define the semantics of for loops, and add cases for for loops as needed so that all the proofs in this file are accepted by Coq.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐