SmallstepSmall-step Operational Semantics
Require Import Coq.Arith.Arith.
Require Import Coq.Arith.EqNat.
Require Import Coq.omega.Omega.
Require Import Coq.Lists.List.
Import ListNotations.
Require Import SfLib.
Require Import Maps.
Require Import Imp.
The evaluators we have seen so far (e.g., the ones for
aexps, bexps, and commands) have been formulated in a
"big-step" style: they specify how a given expression can be
evaluated to its final value (or a command plus a store to a final
store) "all in one big step."
This style is simple and natural for many purposes — indeed,
Gilles Kahn, who popularized it, called it natural semantics.
But there are some things it does not do well. In particular, it
does not give us a natural way of talking about concurrent
programming languages, where the semantics of a program — i.e.,
the essence of how it behaves — is not just which input states
get mapped to which output states, but also includes the
intermediate states that it passes through along the way, since
these states can also be observed by concurrently executing code.
Another shortcoming of the big-step style is more technical, but
critical in many situations. Suppose we want to define a variant
of Imp where variables could hold either numbers or lists of
numbers. In the syntax of this extended language, it will be
possible to write strange expressions like 2 + nil, and our
semantics for arithmetic expressions will then need to say
something about how such expressions behave. One possibility is
to maintain the convention that every arithmetic expressions
evaluates to some number by choosing some way of viewing a list as
a number — e.g., by specifying that a list should be interpreted
as 0 when it occurs in a context expecting a number. But this
is really a bit of a hack.
A much more natural approach is simply to say that the behavior of
an expression like 2+nil is undefined — i.e., it doesn't
evaluate to any result at all. And we can easily do this: we just
have to formulate aeval and beval as Inductive propositions
rather than Fixpoints, so that we can make them partial functions
instead of total ones.
Now, however, we encounter a serious deficiency. In this
language, a command might fail to map a given starting state to
any ending state for two quite different reasons: either because
the execution gets into an infinite loop or because, at some
point, the program tries to do an operation that makes no sense,
such as adding a number to a list, so that none of the evaluation
rules can be applied.
These two outcomes — nontermination vs. getting stuck in an
erroneous configuration — are quite different. In particular, we
want to allow the first (permitting the possibility of infinite
loops is the price we pay for the convenience of programming with
general looping constructs like while) but prevent the
second (which is just wrong), for example by adding some form of
typechecking to the language. Indeed, this will be a major
topic for the rest of the course. As a first step, we need a way
of presenting the semantics that allows us to distinguish
nontermination from erroneous "stuck states."
So, for lots of reasons, we'd like to have a finer-grained way of
defining and reasoning about program behaviors. This is the topic
of the present chapter. We replace the "big-step" eval relation
with a "small-step" relation that specifies, for a given program,
how the "atomic steps" of computation are performed.
A Toy Language
Here is a standard evaluator for this language, written in
the big-step style that we've been using up to this point.
Here is the same evaluator, written in exactly the same
style, but formulated as an inductively defined relation. Again,
we use the notation t ⇓ n for "t evaluates to n."
(E_Const) | |
C n ⇓ n |
t1 ⇓ n1 | |
t2 ⇓ n2 | (E_Plus) |
P t1 t2 ⇓ n1 + n2 |
Reserved Notation " t '⇓' n " (at level 50, left associativity).
Inductive eval : tm → nat → Prop :=
| E_Const : ∀n,
C n ⇓ n
| E_Plus : ∀t1 t2 n1 n2,
t1 ⇓ n1 →
t2 ⇓ n2 →
P t1 t2 ⇓ (n1 + n2)
where " t '⇓' n " := (eval t n).
C n ⇓ n
| E_Plus : ∀t1 t2 n1 n2,
t1 ⇓ n1 →
t2 ⇓ n2 →
P t1 t2 ⇓ (n1 + n2)
where " t '⇓' n " := (eval t n).
Module SimpleArith1.
Now, here is the corresponding small-step evaluation relation.
(ST_PlusConstConst) | |
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2) |
t1 ⇒ t1' | (ST_Plus1) |
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2 |
t2 ⇒ t2' | (ST_Plus2) |
P (C n1) t2 ⇒ P (C n1) t2' |
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
| ST_Plus2 : ∀n1 t2 t2',
t2 ⇒ t2' →
P (C n1) t2 ⇒ P (C n1) t2'
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Things to notice:
Let's pause and check a couple of examples of reasoning with
the step relation...
If t1 can take a step to t1', then P t1 t2 steps
to P t1' t2:
- We are defining just a single reduction step, in which
one P node is replaced by its value.
- Each step finds the leftmost P node that is ready to
go (both of its operands are constants) and rewrites it in
place. The first rule tells how to rewrite this P node
itself; the other two rules tell how to find it.
- A term that is just a constant cannot take a step.
Exercise: 1 star (test_step_2)
Right-hand sides of sums can take a step only when the left-hand side is finished: if t2 can take a step to t2', then P (C n) t2 steps to P (C n) t2':Example test_step_2 :
P
(C 0)
(P
(C 2)
(P (C 0) (C 3)))
⇒
P
(C 0)
(P
(C 2)
(C (0 + 3))).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Relations
Should we be getting this (and deterministic, multi, etc.)
from the standard library? Arguably yes, though the naming in the
library is awkward in places.
Our main examples of such relations in this chapter will be
the single-step reduction relation, ⇒, and its multi-step
variant, ⇒* (defined below), but there are many other
examples — e.g., the "equals," "less than," "less than or equal
to," and "is the square of" relations on numbers, and the "prefix
of" relation on lists and strings.
One simple property of the ⇒ relation is that, like the
big-step evaluation relation for Imp, it is deterministic.
Theorem: For each t, there is at most one t' such that t
steps to t' (t ⇒ t' is provable). Formally, this is the
same as saying that ⇒ is deterministic.
Proof sketch: We show that if x steps to both y1 and
y2, then y1 and y2 are equal, by induction on a derivation
of step x y1. There are several cases to consider, depending on
the last rule used in this derivation and the last rule in the
given derivation of step x y2.
- If both are ST_PlusConstConst, the result is immediate.
- The cases when both derivations end with ST_Plus1 or
ST_Plus2 follow by the induction hypothesis.
- It cannot happen that one is ST_PlusConstConst and the other
is ST_Plus1 or ST_Plus2, since this would imply that x
has the form P t1 t2 where both t1 and t2 are
constants (by ST_PlusConstConst) and one of t1 or t2
has the form P _.
- Similarly, it cannot happen that one is ST_Plus1 and the other is ST_Plus2, since this would imply that x has the form P t1 t2 where t1 has both the form P t11 t12 and the form C n. ☐
Definition deterministic {X: Type} (R: relation X) :=
∀x y1 y2 : X, R x y1 → R x y2 → y1 = y2.
Module SimpleArith2.
Import SimpleArith1.
Theorem step_deterministic:
deterministic step.
Proof.
unfold deterministic. intros x y1 y2 Hy1 Hy2.
generalize dependent y2.
induction Hy1; intros y2 Hy2.
- (* ST_PlusConstConst *) inversion Hy2.
+ (* ST_PlusConstConst *) reflexivity.
+ (* ST_Plus1 *) inversion H2.
+ (* ST_Plus2 *) inversion H2.
- (* ST_Plus1 *) inversion Hy2.
+ (* ST_PlusConstConst *) rewrite ← H0 in Hy1. inversion Hy1.
+ (* ST_Plus1 *)
rewrite ← (IHHy1 t1'0).
reflexivity. assumption.
+ (* ST_Plus2 *) rewrite ← H in Hy1. inversion Hy1.
- (* ST_Plus2 *) inversion Hy2.
+ (* ST_PlusConstConst *) rewrite ← H1 in Hy1. inversion Hy1.
+ (* ST_Plus1 *) inversion H2.
+ (* ST_Plus2 *)
rewrite ← (IHHy1 t2'0).
reflexivity. assumption.
Qed.
There is some annoying repetition in this proof. Each use of
inversion Hy2 results in three subcases, only one of which is
relevant (the one that matches the current case in the induction
on Hy1). The other two subcases need to be dismissed by finding
the contradiction among the hypotheses and doing inversion on it.
The tactic solve by inversion, which is defined in the small
accompanying file SfLib.v, can be helpful in such cases. It
will solve the goal if it can be solved by inverting some
hypothesis; otherwise, it fails. (The variants solve by
inversion 2 and solve by inversion 3 that work if two or three
consecutive inversions will solve the goal.)
Let's see how a proof of the previous theorem can be simplified
using this tactic...
Theorem step_deterministic_alt: deterministic step.
Proof.
intros x y1 y2 Hy1 Hy2.
generalize dependent y2.
induction Hy1; intros y2 Hy2;
inversion Hy2; subst; try (solve by inversion).
- (* ST_PlusConstConst *) reflexivity.
- (* ST_Plus1 *)
apply IHHy1 in H2. rewrite H2. reflexivity.
- (* ST_Plus2 *)
apply IHHy1 in H2. rewrite H2. reflexivity.
Qed.
End SimpleArith2.
Values
- At any moment, the state of the machine is a term.
- A step of the machine is an atomic unit of computation —
here, a single "add" operation.
- The halting states of the machine are ones where there is no more computation to be done.
- Take t as the starting state of the machine.
- Repeatedly use the ⇒ relation to find a sequence of
machine states, starting with t, where each state steps to
the next.
- When no more reduction is possible, "read out" the final state of the machine as the result of execution.
Having introduced the idea of values, we can use it in the
definition of the ⇒ relation to write ST_Plus2 rule in a
slightly more elegant way:
Again, the variable names here carry important information:
by convention, v1 ranges only over values, while t1 and t2
range over arbitrary terms. (Given this convention, the explicit
value hypothesis is arguably redundant. We'll keep it for now,
to maintain a close correspondence between the informal and Coq
versions of the rules, but later on we'll drop it in informal
rules for brevity.)
Here are the formal rules:
(ST_PlusConstConst) | |
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2) |
t1 ⇒ t1' | (ST_Plus1) |
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2 |
value v1 | |
t2 ⇒ t2' | (ST_Plus2) |
P v1 t2 ⇒ P v1 t2' |
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2)
⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
| ST_Plus2 : ∀v1 t2 t2',
value v1 → (* <----- n.b. *)
t2 ⇒ t2' →
P v1 t2 ⇒ P v1 t2'
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (redo_determinism)
As a sanity check on this change, let's re-verify determinism.- If both are ST_PlusConstConst, the result is immediate.
- It cannot happen that one is ST_PlusConstConst and the other
is ST_Plus1 or ST_Plus2, since this would imply that x has
the form P t1 t2 where both t1 and t2 are constants (by
ST_PlusConstConst) and one of t1 or t2 has the form P _.
- Similarly, it cannot happen that one is ST_Plus1 and the other
is ST_Plus2, since this would imply that x has the form P
t1 t2 where t1 both has the form P t11 t12 and is a
value (hence has the form C n).
- The cases when both derivations end with ST_Plus1 or ST_Plus2 follow by the induction hypothesis. ☐
☐
Strong Progress and Normal Forms
- Suppose t = C n. Then t is a value.
- Suppose t = P t1 t2, where (by the IH) t1 either is a value
or can step to some t1', and where t2 is either a value or
can step to some t2'. We must show P t1 t2 is either a value
or steps to some t'.
- If t1 and t2 are both values, then t can take a step, by
ST_PlusConstConst.
- If t1 is a value and t2 can take a step, then so can t,
by ST_Plus2.
- If t1 can take a step, then so can t, by ST_Plus1. ☐
- If t1 and t2 are both values, then t can take a step, by
ST_PlusConstConst.
Theorem strong_progress : ∀t,
value t ∨ (∃t', t ⇒ t').
Proof.
induction t.
- (* C *) left. apply v_const.
- (* P *) right. inversion IHt1.
+ (* l *) inversion IHt2.
* (* l *) inversion H. inversion H0.
∃(C (n + n0)).
apply ST_PlusConstConst.
* (* r *) inversion H0 as [t' H1].
∃(P t1 t').
apply ST_Plus2. apply H. apply H1.
+ (* r *) inversion H as [t' H0].
∃(P t' t2).
apply ST_Plus1. apply H0. Qed.
induction t.
- (* C *) left. apply v_const.
- (* P *) right. inversion IHt1.
+ (* l *) inversion IHt2.
* (* l *) inversion H. inversion H0.
∃(C (n + n0)).
apply ST_PlusConstConst.
* (* r *) inversion H0 as [t' H1].
∃(P t1 t').
apply ST_Plus2. apply H. apply H1.
+ (* r *) inversion H as [t' H0].
∃(P t' t2).
apply ST_Plus1. apply H0. Qed.
This important property is called strong progress, because
every term either is a value or can "make progress" by stepping to
some other term. (The qualifier "strong" distinguishes it from a
more refined version that we'll see in later chapters, called
just progress.)
The idea of "making progress" can be extended to tell us something
interesting about values: in this language, values are exactly the
terms that cannot make progress in this sense.
To state this observation formally, let's begin by giving a name
to terms that cannot make progress. We'll call them normal
forms.
Note that this definition specifies what it is to be a normal form
for an arbitrary relation R over an arbitrary set X, not
just for the particular single-step reduction relation over terms
that we are interested in at the moment. We'll re-use the same
terminology for talking about other relations later in the
course.
We can use this terminology to generalize the observation we made
in the strong progress theorem: in this language, normal forms and
values are actually the same thing.
Lemma value_is_nf : ∀v,
value v → normal_form step v.
Proof.
unfold normal_form. intros v H. inversion H.
intros contra. inversion contra. inversion H1.
Qed.
unfold normal_form. intros v H. inversion H.
intros contra. inversion contra. inversion H1.
Qed.
Lemma nf_is_value : ∀t,
normal_form step t → value t.
Proof. (* a corollary of strong_progress... *)
unfold normal_form. intros t H.
assert (G : value t ∨ ∃t', t ⇒ t').
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply strong_progress. }
inversion G.
+ (* l *) apply H0.
+ (* r *) exfalso. apply H. assumption. Qed.
unfold normal_form. intros t H.
assert (G : value t ∨ ∃t', t ⇒ t').
{ (* Proof of assertion *) apply strong_progress. }
inversion G.
+ (* l *) apply H0.
+ (* r *) exfalso. apply H. assumption. Qed.
Corollary nf_same_as_value : ∀t,
normal_form step t ↔ value t.
Why is this interesting?
It's interesting, because value is a syntactic concept — it is
defined by looking at the form of a term — while normal_form is
a semantic one — it is defined by looking at how the term steps.
It is not obvious that these concepts should coincide! Indeed, we
could easily have written the definitions so that they would not
coincide.
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (value_not_same_as_normal_form)
We might, for example, mistakenly define value so that it includes some terms that are not finished reducing. (Even if you don't work this exercise and the following ones in Coq, make sure you can think of an example of such a term.)Module Temp1.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_const : ∀n, value (C n)
| v_funny : ∀t1 n2, (* <---- *)
value (P t1 (C n2)).
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
| ST_Plus2 : ∀v1 t2 t2',
value v1 →
t2 ⇒ t2' →
P v1 t2 ⇒ P v1 t2'
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Lemma value_not_same_as_normal_form :
∃v, value v ∧ ¬ normal_form step v.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 2 stars, optional (value_not_same_as_normal_form)
Alternatively, we might mistakenly define step so that it permits something designated as a value to reduce further.Module Temp2.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_const : ∀n, value (C n).
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_Funny : ∀n, (* <---- *)
C n ⇒ P (C n) (C 0)
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
| ST_Plus2 : ∀v1 t2 t2',
value v1 →
t2 ⇒ t2' →
P v1 t2 ⇒ P v1 t2'
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Lemma value_not_same_as_normal_form :
∃v, value v ∧ ¬ normal_form step v.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (value_not_same_as_normal_form')
Finally, we might define value and step so that there is some term that is not a value but that cannot take a step in the step relation. Such terms are said to be stuck. In this case this is caused by a mistake in the semantics, but we will also see situations where, even in a correct language definition, it makes sense to allow some terms to be stuck.Module Temp3.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_const : ∀n, value (C n).
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
(Note that ST_Plus2 is missing.)
Lemma value_not_same_as_normal_form :
∃t, ¬ value t ∧ normal_form step t.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Here is another very simple language whose terms, instead of being
just addition expressions and numbers, are just the booleans true
and false and a conditional expression...
Inductive tm : Type :=
| ttrue : tm
| tfalse : tm
| tif : tm → tm → tm → tm.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_true : value ttrue
| v_false : value tfalse.
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_IfTrue : ∀t1 t2,
tif ttrue t1 t2 ⇒ t1
| ST_IfFalse : ∀t1 t2,
tif tfalse t1 t2 ⇒ t2
| ST_If : ∀t1 t1' t2 t3,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
tif t1 t2 t3 ⇒ tif t1' t2 t3
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Exercise: 1 star (smallstep_bools)
Which of the following propositions are provable? (This is just a thought exercise, but for an extra challenge feel free to prove your answers in Coq.)Definition bool_step_prop1 :=
tfalse ⇒ tfalse.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
Definition bool_step_prop2 :=
tif
ttrue
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
(tif tfalse tfalse tfalse)
⇒
ttrue.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
Definition bool_step_prop3 :=
tif
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
tfalse
⇒
tif
ttrue
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
tfalse.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (progress_bool)
Just as we proved a progress theorem for plus expressions, we can do so for boolean expressions, as well.
☐
Exercise: 2 stars (smallstep_bool_shortcut)
Suppose we want to add a "short circuit" to the step relation for boolean expressions, so that it can recognize when the then and else branches of a conditional are the same value (either ttrue or tfalse) and reduce the whole conditional to this value in a single step, even if the guard has not yet been reduced to a value. For example, we would like this proposition to be provable:
tif
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
tfalse
tfalse
⇒
tfalse.
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
tfalse
tfalse
⇒
tfalse.
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_IfTrue : ∀t1 t2,
tif ttrue t1 t2 ⇒ t1
| ST_IfFalse : ∀t1 t2,
tif tfalse t1 t2 ⇒ t2
| ST_If : ∀t1 t1' t2 t3,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
tif t1 t2 t3 ⇒ tif t1' t2 t3
(* FILL IN HERE *)
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Definition bool_step_prop4 :=
tif
(tif ttrue ttrue ttrue)
tfalse
tfalse
⇒
tfalse.
Example bool_step_prop4_holds :
bool_step_prop4.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (properties_of_altered_step)
It can be shown that the determinism and strong progress theorems for the step relation in the lecture notes also hold for the definition of step given above. After we add the clause ST_ShortCircuit...- Is the step relation still deterministic? Write yes or no and
briefly (1 sentence) explain your answer.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
- Does a strong progress theorem hold? Write yes or no and
briefly (1 sentence) explain your answer.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
- In general, is there any way we could cause strong progress to fail if we took away one or more constructors from the original step relation? Write yes or no and briefly (1 sentence) explain your answer.
☐
Multi-Step Reduction
- First, we define a multi-step reduction relation ⇒*, which
relates terms t and t' if t can reach t' by any number
(including zero) of single reduction steps.
- Then we define a "result" of a term t as a normal form that t can reach by multi-step reduction.
Since we'll want to reuse the idea of multi-step reduction many
times, let's take a little extra trouble and define it
generically.
Given a relation R, we define a relation multi R, called the
multi-step closure of R as follows.
Inductive multi {X:Type} (R: relation X) : relation X :=
| multi_refl : ∀(x : X), multi R x x
| multi_step : ∀(x y z : X),
R x y →
multi R y z →
multi R x z.
(In the Rel chapter and the Coq standard library, this relation
is called clos_refl_trans_1n. We give it a shorter name here
for the sake of readability.)
The effect of this definition is that multi R relates two
elements x and y if
We write ⇒* for the multi step relation on terms.
- x = y, or
- R x y, or
- there is some nonempty sequence z1, z2, ..., zn such that
R x z1
R z1 z2
...
R zn y.
The relation multi R has several crucial properties.
First, it is obviously reflexive (that is, ∀ x, multi R x
x). In the case of the ⇒* (i.e., multi step) relation, the
intuition is that a term can execute to itself by taking zero
steps of execution.
Second, it contains R — that is, single-step executions are a
particular case of multi-step executions. (It is this fact that
justifies the word "closure" in the term "multi-step closure of
R.")
Third, multi R is transitive.
Theorem multi_trans :
∀(X:Type) (R: relation X) (x y z : X),
multi R x y →
multi R y z →
multi R x z.
Proof.
intros X R x y z G H.
induction G.
- (* multi_refl *) assumption.
- (* multi_step *)
apply multi_step with y. assumption.
apply IHG. assumption. Qed.
intros X R x y z G H.
induction G.
- (* multi_refl *) assumption.
- (* multi_step *)
apply multi_step with y. assumption.
apply IHG. assumption. Qed.
In particular, for the multi step relation on terms, if
t1⇒*t2 and t2⇒*t3, then t1⇒*t3.
Lemma test_multistep_1:
P
(P (C 0) (C 3))
(P (C 2) (C 4))
⇒*
C ((0 + 3) + (2 + 4)).
Proof.
apply multi_step with
(P
(C (0 + 3))
(P (C 2) (C 4))).
apply ST_Plus1. apply ST_PlusConstConst.
apply multi_step with
(P
(C (0 + 3))
(C (2 + 4))).
apply ST_Plus2. apply v_const.
apply ST_PlusConstConst.
apply multi_R.
apply ST_PlusConstConst. Qed.
Here's an alternate proof of the same fact that uses eapply to
avoid explicitly constructing all the intermediate terms.
Lemma test_multistep_1':
P
(P (C 0) (C 3))
(P (C 2) (C 4))
⇒*
C ((0 + 3) + (2 + 4)).
Proof.
eapply multi_step. apply ST_Plus1. apply ST_PlusConstConst.
eapply multi_step. apply ST_Plus2. apply v_const.
apply ST_PlusConstConst.
eapply multi_step. apply ST_PlusConstConst.
apply multi_refl. Qed.
Lemma test_multistep_4:
P
(C 0)
(P
(C 2)
(P (C 0) (C 3)))
⇒*
P
(C 0)
(C (2 + (0 + 3))).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
P
(C 0)
(P
(C 2)
(P (C 0) (C 3)))
⇒*
P
(C 0)
(C (2 + (0 + 3))).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Normal Forms Again
Definition step_normal_form := normal_form step.
Definition normal_form_of (t t' : tm) :=
(t ⇒* t' ∧ step_normal_form t').
We have already seen that, for our language, single-step reduction is
deterministic — i.e., a given term can take a single step in
at most one way. It follows from this that, if t can reach
a normal form, then this normal form is unique. In other words, we
can actually pronounce normal_form t t' as "t' is the
normal form of t."
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (normal_forms_unique)
Theorem normal_forms_unique:
deterministic normal_form_of.
Proof.
(* We recommend using this initial setup as-is! *)
unfold deterministic. unfold normal_form_of.
intros x y1 y2 P1 P2.
inversion P1 as [P11 P12]; clear P1.
inversion P2 as [P21 P22]; clear P2.
generalize dependent y2.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
deterministic normal_form_of.
Proof.
(* We recommend using this initial setup as-is! *)
unfold deterministic. unfold normal_form_of.
intros x y1 y2 P1 P2.
inversion P1 as [P11 P12]; clear P1.
inversion P2 as [P21 P22]; clear P2.
generalize dependent y2.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Indeed, something stronger is true for this language (though not
for all languages): the reduction of any term t will
eventually reach a normal form — i.e., normal_form_of is a
total function. Formally, we say the step relation is
normalizing.
To prove that step is normalizing, we need a couple of lemmas.
First, we observe that, if t reduces to t' in many steps, then
the same sequence of reduction steps within t is also possible
when t appears as the left-hand child of a P node, and
similarly when t appears as the right-hand child of a P
node whose left-hand child is a value.
Lemma multistep_congr_1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒* t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒* P t1' t2.
Proof.
intros t1 t1' t2 H. induction H.
- (* multi_refl *) apply multi_refl.
- (* multi_step *) apply multi_step with (P y t2).
apply ST_Plus1. apply H.
apply IHmulti. Qed.
intros t1 t1' t2 H. induction H.
- (* multi_refl *) apply multi_refl.
- (* multi_step *) apply multi_step with (P y t2).
apply ST_Plus1. apply H.
apply IHmulti. Qed.
Lemma multistep_congr_2 : ∀t1 t2 t2',
value t1 →
t2 ⇒* t2' →
P t1 t2 ⇒* P t1 t2'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
value t1 →
t2 ⇒* t2' →
P t1 t2 ⇒* P t1 t2'.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
With these lemmas in hand, the main proof is a straightforward
induction.
Theorem: The step function is normalizing — i.e., for every
t there exists some t' such that t steps to t' and t' is
a normal form.
Proof sketch: By induction on terms. There are two cases to
consider:
- t = C n for some n. Here t doesn't take a step, and we
have t' = t. We can derive the left-hand side by reflexivity
and the right-hand side by observing (a) that values are normal
forms (by nf_same_as_value) and (b) that t is a value (by
v_const).
- t = P t1 t2 for some t1 and t2. By the IH, t1 and t2
have normal forms t1' and t2'. Recall that normal forms are
values (by nf_same_as_value); we know that t1' = C n1 and
t2' = C n2, for some n1 and n2. We can combine the ⇒*
derivations for t1 and t2 using multi_congr_1 and
multi_congr_1 to prove that P t1 t2 reduces in many steps to
C (n1 + n2).
Theorem step_normalizing :
normalizing step.
Proof.
unfold normalizing.
induction t.
- (* C *)
∃(C n).
split.
+ (* l *) apply multi_refl.
+ (* r *)
(* We can use rewrite with "iff" statements, not
just equalities: *)
rewrite nf_same_as_value. apply v_const.
- (* P *)
inversion IHt1 as [t1' H1]; clear IHt1. inversion IHt2 as [t2' H2]; clear IHt2.
inversion H1 as [H11 H12]; clear H1. inversion H2 as [H21 H22]; clear H2.
rewrite nf_same_as_value in H12. rewrite nf_same_as_value in H22.
inversion H12 as [n1]. inversion H22 as [n2].
rewrite ← H in H11.
rewrite ← H0 in H21.
∃(C (n1 + n2)).
split.
+ (* l *)
apply multi_trans with (P (C n1) t2).
apply multistep_congr_1. apply H11.
apply multi_trans with
(P (C n1) (C n2)).
apply multistep_congr_2. apply v_const. apply H21.
apply multi_R. apply ST_PlusConstConst.
+ (* r *)
rewrite nf_same_as_value. apply v_const. Qed.
unfold normalizing.
induction t.
- (* C *)
∃(C n).
split.
+ (* l *) apply multi_refl.
+ (* r *)
(* We can use rewrite with "iff" statements, not
just equalities: *)
rewrite nf_same_as_value. apply v_const.
- (* P *)
inversion IHt1 as [t1' H1]; clear IHt1. inversion IHt2 as [t2' H2]; clear IHt2.
inversion H1 as [H11 H12]; clear H1. inversion H2 as [H21 H22]; clear H2.
rewrite nf_same_as_value in H12. rewrite nf_same_as_value in H22.
inversion H12 as [n1]. inversion H22 as [n2].
rewrite ← H in H11.
rewrite ← H0 in H21.
∃(C (n1 + n2)).
split.
+ (* l *)
apply multi_trans with (P (C n1) t2).
apply multistep_congr_1. apply H11.
apply multi_trans with
(P (C n1) (C n2)).
apply multistep_congr_2. apply v_const. apply H21.
apply multi_R. apply ST_PlusConstConst.
+ (* r *)
rewrite nf_same_as_value. apply v_const. Qed.
Equivalence of Big-Step and Small-Step Reduction
Exercise: 3 stars (eval__multistep)
The key ideas in the proof can be seen in the following picture:
To formalize this intuition, you'll need to use the congruence
lemmas from above (you might want to review them now, so that
you'll be able to recognize when they are useful), plus some basic
properties of ⇒*: that it is reflexive, transitive, and
includes ⇒.
P t1 t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus1)
P t1' t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus1)
P t1'' t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus1)
...
P (C n1) t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
P (C n1) t2' ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
P (C n1) t2'' ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
...
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ (by ST_PlusConstConst)
C (n1 + n2)
That is, the multistep reduction of a term of the form P t1 t2
proceeds in three phases:
P t1' t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus1)
P t1'' t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus1)
...
P (C n1) t2 ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
P (C n1) t2' ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
P (C n1) t2'' ⇒ (by ST_Plus2)
...
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ (by ST_PlusConstConst)
C (n1 + n2)
- First, we use ST_Plus1 some number of times to reduce t1 to a normal form, which must (by nf_same_as_value) be a term of the form C n1 for some n1.
- Next, we use ST_Plus2 some number of times to reduce t2 to a normal form, which must again be a term of the form C n2 for some n2.
- Finally, we use ST_PlusConstConst one time to reduce P (C n1) (C n2) to C (n1 + n2).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
For the other direction, we need one lemma, which establishes a
relation between single-step reduction and big-step evaluation.
Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (eval__multistep_inf)
Write a detailed informal version of the proof of eval__multistep.☐
Exercise: 3 stars (step__eval)
Lemma step__eval : ∀t t' n,
t ⇒ t' →
t' ⇓ n →
t ⇓ n.
Proof.
intros t t' n Hs. generalize dependent n.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
t ⇒ t' →
t' ⇓ n →
t ⇓ n.
Proof.
intros t t' n Hs. generalize dependent n.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
The fact that small-step reduction implies big-step is now
straightforward to prove, once it is stated correctly.
The proof proceeds by induction on the multi-step reduction
sequence that is buried in the hypothesis normal_form_of t t'. Make sure you understand the statement before you start to
work on the proof.
Exercise: 3 stars (multistep__eval)
Theorem multistep__eval : ∀t t',
normal_form_of t t' → ∃n, t' = C n ∧ t ⇓ n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
normal_form_of t t' → ∃n, t' = C n ∧ t ⇓ n.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
Additional Exercises
Exercise: 3 stars, optional (interp_tm)
Remember that we also defined big-step evaluation of terms as a function evalF. Prove that it is equivalent to the existing semantics. (Hint: we just proved that eval and multistep are equivalent, so logically it doesn't matter which you choose. One will be easier than the other, though!)
☐
Exercise: 4 stars (combined_properties)
We've considered arithmetic and conditional expressions separately. This exercise explores how the two interact.Module Combined.
Inductive tm : Type :=
| C : nat → tm
| P : tm → tm → tm
| ttrue : tm
| tfalse : tm
| tif : tm → tm → tm → tm.
Inductive value : tm → Prop :=
| v_const : ∀n, value (C n)
| v_true : value ttrue
| v_false : value tfalse.
Reserved Notation " t '⇒' t' " (at level 40).
Inductive step : tm → tm → Prop :=
| ST_PlusConstConst : ∀n1 n2,
P (C n1) (C n2) ⇒ C (n1 + n2)
| ST_Plus1 : ∀t1 t1' t2,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
P t1 t2 ⇒ P t1' t2
| ST_Plus2 : ∀v1 t2 t2',
value v1 →
t2 ⇒ t2' →
P v1 t2 ⇒ P v1 t2'
| ST_IfTrue : ∀t1 t2,
tif ttrue t1 t2 ⇒ t1
| ST_IfFalse : ∀t1 t2,
tif tfalse t1 t2 ⇒ t2
| ST_If : ∀t1 t1' t2 t3,
t1 ⇒ t1' →
tif t1 t2 t3 ⇒ tif t1' t2 t3
where " t '⇒' t' " := (step t t').
Earlier, we separately proved for both plus- and if-expressions...
- that the step relation was deterministic, and
- a strong progress lemma, stating that every term is either a value or can take a step.
(* FILL IN HERE *)
☐
Small-Step Imp
We are not actually going to bother to define boolean
values, since they aren't needed in the definition of ⇒b
below (why?), though they might be if our language were a bit
larger (why?).
Reserved Notation " t '/' st '⇒a' t' " (at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive astep : state → aexp → aexp → Prop :=
| AS_Id : ∀st i,
AId i / st ⇒a ANum (st i)
| AS_Plus : ∀st n1 n2,
APlus (ANum n1) (ANum n2) / st ⇒a ANum (n1 + n2)
| AS_Plus1 : ∀st a1 a1' a2,
a1 / st ⇒a a1' →
(APlus a1 a2) / st ⇒a (APlus a1' a2)
| AS_Plus2 : ∀st v1 a2 a2',
aval v1 →
a2 / st ⇒a a2' →
(APlus v1 a2) / st ⇒a (APlus v1 a2')
| AS_Minus : ∀st n1 n2,
(AMinus (ANum n1) (ANum n2)) / st ⇒a (ANum (minus n1 n2))
| AS_Minus1 : ∀st a1 a1' a2,
a1 / st ⇒a a1' →
(AMinus a1 a2) / st ⇒a (AMinus a1' a2)
| AS_Minus2 : ∀st v1 a2 a2',
aval v1 →
a2 / st ⇒a a2' →
(AMinus v1 a2) / st ⇒a (AMinus v1 a2')
| AS_Mult : ∀st n1 n2,
(AMult (ANum n1) (ANum n2)) / st ⇒a (ANum (mult n1 n2))
| AS_Mult1 : ∀st a1 a1' a2,
a1 / st ⇒a a1' →
(AMult (a1) (a2)) / st ⇒a (AMult (a1') (a2))
| AS_Mult2 : ∀st v1 a2 a2',
aval v1 →
a2 / st ⇒a a2' →
(AMult v1 a2) / st ⇒a (AMult v1 a2')
where " t '/' st '⇒a' t' " := (astep st t t').
Reserved Notation " t '/' st '⇒b' t' " (at level 40, st at level 39).
Inductive bstep : state → bexp → bexp → Prop :=
| BS_Eq : ∀st n1 n2,
(BEq (ANum n1) (ANum n2)) / st ⇒b
(if (beq_nat n1 n2) then BTrue else BFalse)
| BS_Eq1 : ∀st a1 a1' a2,
a1 / st ⇒a a1' →
(BEq a1 a2) / st ⇒b (BEq a1' a2)
| BS_Eq2 : ∀st v1 a2 a2',
aval v1 →
a2 / st ⇒a a2' →
(BEq v1 a2) / st ⇒b (BEq v1 a2')
| BS_LtEq : ∀st n1 n2,
(BLe (ANum n1) (ANum n2)) / st ⇒b
(if (leb n1 n2) then BTrue else BFalse)
| BS_LtEq1 : ∀st a1 a1' a2,
a1 / st ⇒a a1' →
(BLe a1 a2) / st ⇒b (BLe a1' a2)
| BS_LtEq2 : ∀st v1 a2 a2',
aval v1 →
a2 / st ⇒a a2' →
(BLe v1 a2) / st ⇒b (BLe v1 (a2'))
| BS_NotTrue : ∀st,
(BNot BTrue) / st ⇒b BFalse
| BS_NotFalse : ∀st,
(BNot BFalse) / st ⇒b BTrue
| BS_NotStep : ∀st b1 b1',
b1 / st ⇒b b1' →
(BNot b1) / st ⇒b (BNot b1')
| BS_AndTrueTrue : ∀st,
(BAnd BTrue BTrue) / st ⇒b BTrue
| BS_AndTrueFalse : ∀st,
(BAnd BTrue BFalse) / st ⇒b BFalse
| BS_AndFalse : ∀st b2,
(BAnd BFalse b2) / st ⇒b BFalse
| BS_AndTrueStep : ∀st b2 b2',
b2 / st ⇒b b2' →
(BAnd BTrue b2) / st ⇒b (BAnd BTrue b2')
| BS_AndStep : ∀st b1 b1' b2,
b1 / st ⇒b b1' →
(BAnd b1 b2) / st ⇒b (BAnd b1' b2)
where " t '/' st '⇒b' t' " := (bstep st t t').
The semantics of commands is the interesting part. We need two
small tricks to make it work:
(There are other ways of achieving the effect of the latter
trick, but they all share the feature that the original WHILE
command needs to be saved somewhere while a single copy of the loop
body is being evaluated.)
- We use SKIP as a "command value" — i.e., a command that
has reached a normal form.
- An assignment command reduces to SKIP (and an updated
state).
- The sequencing command waits until its left-hand
subcommand has reduced to SKIP, then throws it away so
that reduction can continue with the right-hand
subcommand.
- An assignment command reduces to SKIP (and an updated
state).
- We reduce a WHILE command by transforming it into a conditional followed by the same WHILE.
Reserved Notation " t '/' st '⇒' t' '/' st' "
(at level 40, st at level 39, t' at level 39).
Inductive cstep : (com * state) → (com * state) → Prop :=
| CS_AssStep : ∀st i a a',
a / st ⇒a a' →
(i ::= a) / st ⇒ (i ::= a') / st
| CS_Ass : ∀st i n,
(i ::= (ANum n)) / st ⇒ SKIP / (t_update st i n)
| CS_SeqStep : ∀st c1 c1' st' c2,
c1 / st ⇒ c1' / st' →
(c1 ;; c2) / st ⇒ (c1' ;; c2) / st'
| CS_SeqFinish : ∀st c2,
(SKIP ;; c2) / st ⇒ c2 / st
| CS_IfTrue : ∀st c1 c2,
IFB BTrue THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st ⇒ c1 / st
| CS_IfFalse : ∀st c1 c2,
IFB BFalse THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st ⇒ c2 / st
| CS_IfStep : ∀st b b' c1 c2,
b / st ⇒b b' →
IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI / st
⇒ (IFB b' THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st
| CS_While : ∀st b c1,
(WHILE b DO c1 END) / st
⇒ (IFB b THEN (c1;; (WHILE b DO c1 END)) ELSE SKIP FI) / st
where " t '/' st '⇒' t' '/' st' " := (cstep (t,st) (t',st')).
Concurrent Imp
Module CImp.
Inductive com : Type :=
| CSkip : com
| CAss : id → aexp → com
| CSeq : com → com → com
| CIf : bexp → com → com → com
| CWhile : bexp → com → com
(* New: *)
| CPar : com → com → com.
Notation "'SKIP'" :=
CSkip.
Notation "x '::=' a" :=
(CAss x a) (at level 60).
Notation "c1 ;; c2" :=
(CSeq c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'WHILE' b 'DO' c 'END'" :=
(CWhile b c) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'IFB' b 'THEN' c1 'ELSE' c2 'FI'" :=
(CIf b c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Notation "'PAR' c1 'WITH' c2 'END'" :=
(CPar c1 c2) (at level 80, right associativity).
Inductive cstep : (com * state) → (com * state) → Prop :=
(* Old part *)
| CS_AssStep : ∀st i a a',
a / st ⇒a a' →
(i ::= a) / st ⇒ (i ::= a') / st
| CS_Ass : ∀st i n,
(i ::= (ANum n)) / st ⇒ SKIP / (t_update st i n)
| CS_SeqStep : ∀st c1 c1' st' c2,
c1 / st ⇒ c1' / st' →
(c1 ;; c2) / st ⇒ (c1' ;; c2) / st'
| CS_SeqFinish : ∀st c2,
(SKIP ;; c2) / st ⇒ c2 / st
| CS_IfTrue : ∀st c1 c2,
(IFB BTrue THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇒ c1 / st
| CS_IfFalse : ∀st c1 c2,
(IFB BFalse THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st ⇒ c2 / st
| CS_IfStep : ∀st b b' c1 c2,
b /st ⇒b b' →
(IFB b THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st
⇒ (IFB b' THEN c1 ELSE c2 FI) / st
| CS_While : ∀st b c1,
(WHILE b DO c1 END) / st
⇒ (IFB b THEN (c1;; (WHILE b DO c1 END)) ELSE SKIP FI) / st
(* New part: *)
| CS_Par1 : ∀st c1 c1' c2 st',
c1 / st ⇒ c1' / st' →
(PAR c1 WITH c2 END) / st ⇒ (PAR c1' WITH c2 END) / st'
| CS_Par2 : ∀st c1 c2 c2' st',
c2 / st ⇒ c2' / st' →
(PAR c1 WITH c2 END) / st ⇒ (PAR c1 WITH c2' END) / st'
| CS_ParDone : ∀st,
(PAR SKIP WITH SKIP END) / st ⇒ SKIP / st
where " t '/' st '⇒' t' '/' st' " := (cstep (t,st) (t',st')).
Definition cmultistep := multi cstep.
Notation " t '/' st '⇒*' t' '/' st' " :=
(multi cstep (t,st) (t',st'))
(at level 40, st at level 39, t' at level 39).
Among the many interesting properties of this language is the fact
that the following program can terminate with the variable X set
to any value.
Definition par_loop : com :=
PAR
Y ::= ANum 1
WITH
WHILE BEq (AId Y) (ANum 0) DO
X ::= APlus (AId X) (ANum 1)
END
END.
In particular, it can terminate with X set to 0:
Example par_loop_example_0:
∃st',
par_loop / empty_state ⇒* SKIP / st'
∧ st' X = 0.
Proof.
eapply ex_intro. split.
unfold par_loop.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
eapply multi_refl.
reflexivity. Qed.
eapply ex_intro. split.
unfold par_loop.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
eapply multi_refl.
reflexivity. Qed.
It can also terminate with X set to 2:
Example par_loop_example_2:
∃st',
par_loop / empty_state ⇒* SKIP / st'
∧ st' X = 2.
Proof.
eapply ex_intro. split.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfTrue.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqFinish.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfTrue.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1. apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqFinish.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
eapply multi_refl.
reflexivity. Qed.
eapply ex_intro. split.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfTrue.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqFinish.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfTrue.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_AssStep. apply AS_Plus.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqStep.
apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1. apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_SeqFinish.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
eapply multi_refl.
reflexivity. Qed.
Lemma par_body_n__Sn : ∀n st,
st X = n ∧ st Y = 0 →
par_loop / st ⇒* par_loop / (t_update st X (S n)).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
st X = n ∧ st Y = 0 →
par_loop / st ⇒* par_loop / (t_update st X (S n)).
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
Lemma par_body_n : ∀n st,
st X = 0 ∧ st Y = 0 →
∃st',
par_loop / st ⇒* par_loop / st' ∧ st' X = n ∧ st' Y = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
st X = 0 ∧ st Y = 0 →
∃st',
par_loop / st ⇒* par_loop / st' ∧ st' X = n ∧ st' Y = 0.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐
... the above loop can exit with X having any value
whatsoever.
Theorem par_loop_any_X:
∀n, ∃st',
par_loop / empty_state ⇒* SKIP / st'
∧ st' X = n.
Proof.
intros n.
destruct (par_body_n n empty_state).
split; unfold t_update; reflexivity.
rename x into st.
inversion H as [H' [HX HY]]; clear H.
∃(t_update st Y 1). split.
eapply multi_trans with (par_loop,st). apply H'.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1. apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id. rewrite t_update_eq.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
apply multi_refl.
rewrite t_update_neq. assumption. intro X; inversion X.
Qed.
intros n.
destruct (par_body_n n empty_state).
split; unfold t_update; reflexivity.
rename x into st.
inversion H as [H' [HX HY]]; clear H.
∃(t_update st Y 1). split.
eapply multi_trans with (par_loop,st). apply H'.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par1. apply CS_Ass.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_While.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq1. apply AS_Id. rewrite t_update_eq.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfStep.
apply BS_Eq. simpl.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_Par2. apply CS_IfFalse.
eapply multi_step. apply CS_ParDone.
apply multi_refl.
rewrite t_update_neq. assumption. intro X; inversion X.
Qed.
End CImp.
A Small-Step Stack Machine
Definition stack := list nat.
Definition prog := list sinstr.
Inductive stack_step : state → prog * stack → prog * stack → Prop :=
| SS_Push : ∀st stk n p',
stack_step st (SPush n :: p', stk) (p', n :: stk)
| SS_Load : ∀st stk i p',
stack_step st (SLoad i :: p', stk) (p', st i :: stk)
| SS_Plus : ∀st stk n m p',
stack_step st (SPlus :: p', n::m::stk) (p', (m+n)::stk)
| SS_Minus : ∀st stk n m p',
stack_step st (SMinus :: p', n::m::stk) (p', (m-n)::stk)
| SS_Mult : ∀st stk n m p',
stack_step st (SMult :: p', n::m::stk) (p', (m*n)::stk).
Theorem stack_step_deterministic : ∀st,
deterministic (stack_step st).
Definition stack_multistep st := multi (stack_step st).
Exercise: 3 stars, advanced (compiler_is_correct)
Remember the definition of compile for aexp given in the Imp chapter. We want now to prove compile correct with respect to the stack machine.Definition compiler_is_correct_statement : Prop :=
(* FILL IN HERE *) admit.
Theorem compiler_is_correct : compiler_is_correct_statement.
Proof.
(* FILL IN HERE *) Admitted.
☐